Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Culture, Truth, and Science After Lacan

  • Symposium
  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Truth and knowledge are conceptually related and there is a way of construing both that implies that they cannot be solely derived from a description that restricts itself to a set of scientific facts. In the first section of this essay, I analyse truth as a relation between a praxis, ways of knowing, and the world. In the second section, I invoke the third thing—the objective reality on which we triangulate as knowing subjects for the purpose of complex scientific endeavours like medical science and clinical care. Such praxes develop robust methods of “keeping in touch” with disease and illness (like biomarkers). An analysis drawing on philosophical semantics motivates the needed (anti-scientistic) account of meaning and truth (and therefore knowledge) and underpins the following argument: (i) the formulation and dissemination of knowledge rests on language; (ii) language is selective in what it represents in any given situation; (iii) the praxes of a given (sub)culture are based on this selectivity; but (iv) human health and illness involve whole human beings in a human life-world; therefore, (v) medical knowledge should reflectively transcend, where required, biomedical science towards a more inclusive view. Parts three and four argue that a post-structuralist (Lacanian) account of the human subject can avoid both scientism and idealism or unconstrained relativism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The style of truth theory here is based on the work of Alfred Tarski (1944) and is widely accepted in current philosophical accounts of truth.

  2. The footnote in the 1997 Cambridge edition helpfully translates: “[Because of] agreement with a third thing, they agree among themselves” (Kant 1997, B849).

  3. Because our paradigm for thoughts involves their propositional content (as if they had a sentential form), we could call this a propositional structure, even though that idea is more comfortable in analytic philosophy than continental philosophy where the dependence of language (and some would say thought) on speech is more widely accepted (Vygotsky 1962).

  4. Lacan uses tuche, variously translated as contingency, chance, or luck, to indicate the mismatch between the orderly world of grammar or thought and the raw Dionysian power of the world in which we find ourselves and to put an interesting twist on the Freudian “thing,” which Freud himself directly borrowed from the Kantian “ding an sich” (the thing in itself that becomes the third thing to which two subjects co-refer). This is, I find, one of the most difficult areas of his thought because it inflects subjectivity away from discursive articulation.

  5. Wittgenstein reflects this structuralist thought when he remarks that meanings reflect the post where the word is stationed in language and grammar 1953, ¶29).

References

  • Armstrong, D.M. 2004. Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark-Grill, M. 2010. When listening to the people: Lessons from complementary and alternative medicine (CAM) for bioethics. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 7(1): 71–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 2001. Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure, F. 1972. Course in general linguistics. Edited by C. Bally and A. Sechehaye, translated by R. Harris. Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court. Originally published as Cours de linguistique générale (London: Duckworth, 1983).

  • Evans, G. 1982. The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. 1984. In The Foucault reader, Edited by P. Rabinow. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. 2008. Introduction to Kant’s anthropology. Los Angeles: Semiotexte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1980. Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Edited by P. Geach and M. Black. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 1992. Representation meaning and thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 2004. Bioethics in the clinic: Hippocratic reflections. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 2008. Subjectivity and being somebody: Human identity and neuroethics. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 2009a. The mind and its discontents, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 2009b. Indigenous knowledges: Circumspection, metaphysics, and scientific ontologies. Sites 6(1): 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 2014. Concepts, consciousness and counting by pigeons. Mind 123(492): 1147–1153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G., and J. McMillan. 2001. Consciousness and intentionality. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harre, R., and G. Gillett. 1994. The discursive mind. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. 1977. The question concerning technology. Translated by W. Lovitt. New York: Garland.

  • Kant, I. 1997. The critique of pure reason. Translated by P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Originally published as Critik der reinen vernunft (Riga: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, 1789).

  • Kripke, S.A. 1979. A puzzle about belief. In Meaning and use, Edited by E. Margolit, 61–84. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. 1977. Ecrits. New York: Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. 1979. The four fundamental concepts of psycho-analysis. Translated by A. Sheridan. London: Penguin.

  • Locke, J. 1975. An essay concerning human understanding. Edited by P. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon. Originally published as An essay concerning human understanding (London: William Tegg, 1689).

  • Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2011. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 34(2): 57–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W. 1981. The rationality of science. Boston: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 2010. The cognitive niche: Coevolution of intelligence, sociality and language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107(S2): 8993–8999.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Quinton, A. 1967. The problem of perception. In The philosophy of perception, Edited by G. Warnock, 61–84. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 2007. On the nature of acquaintance. In Logic and knowledge, Edited by B. Russell, 125–174. London: Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönbaumsfeld, G. 2007. A confusion of the spheres: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on philosophy and religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. 1997. Empiricism and the philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. 1944. The semantic conception of truth: And the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4(3): 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2014. A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraasen, B. 2008. Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L.S. 1962. Thought and language. Translated by E. Hanfmann and G. Vakar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Originally published as Myshlenie i rech’ (Moscow: Sotsekgiz, 1934).

  • Wikipedia. 2014. Causal filter. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Causal_filter. Accessed October 10, 2015.

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell. Originally published as Philosophische untersuchungen (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Grant Gillett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gillett, G. Culture, Truth, and Science After Lacan. Bioethical Inquiry 12, 633–644 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-015-9664-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-015-9664-2

Keywords

Navigation