Proportionality leads a double life. Criminal law theorists have noted a range of severe difficulties for any attempt to proportion punishment severity to crime seriousness. It requires selecting a common metric of gravity across all crimes and punishments. This metric must offer both relative and absolute proportionality judgements. No-one claims to have resolved these difficulties. And yet, despite this, many sentencing codes purport to make such proportionality judgements with little apparent difficulty. In practice, almost all agree that murder is more serious than robbery, which in turn is more serious than petty theft. Setting a relative scale of gravity has not proven controversial. There’s less consensus as to how to anchor this scale to absolute figures. But many sentencing codes have been enacted without too much dissent. What explains the mismatch between this practical ease and those theoretical difficulties? The answer, I think, is that criminal law theorists are ambitious. They want to uncover a full theory of proportionality which can explain these proportionality judgements (or explain why they are mistaken).Footnote 1

Unfortunately, no full theory has resolved those theoretical difficulties. I will not propose another full theory of proportionality. Instead, I’ll start with obvious and uncontroversial proportionality judgements, and then work up to a wider principle from there. This is easier said than done. Only a small range of punishments are precisely proportionate, whereas everything else is disproportionate. So, I will only offer approximate judgements.Footnote 2 In practice, most theorists are concerned with disproportionately severe punishments, not those that are disproportionately lenient. So, I will only consider cases where some punishment is obviously not disproportionately severe. (Throughout, this is what I mean by ‘proportionate’). Within these limitations, I’ll generalise from uncontroversial cases to reach a lower bound for proportionate punishment. That is the aim of Sect. 1.

This lower bound will not apply to every potential punishment, from parental discipline through to international sanctions. That would be too ambitious. Instead, I’ll limit my attention only to punishments imposed in response to criminal wrongs committed without any defence.Footnote 3 (I’ll mention other limitations in Sect. 2).

In the final sections, I’ll flesh out what this lower bound implies in practice.

In addition to avoiding a full theory of proportionality, I also want to avoid reliance on any particular theory of (the justification for) punishment. I want to start with an ecumenically uncontroversial case of proportionate punishment. This requires some defending. Isn’t it true that whether some punishment is proportionate to a crime depends on the underlying theory of punishment at work?Footnote 4 If punishment aims to impose deserved suffering on the offender, then it should inflict a proportionate amount of suffering. By contrast, if punishment aims to deter future potential wrongdoers, then it is proportionate insofar as it causes the right amount of deterrence. These metrics conflict. Hence: proportionality judgements cannot be neutral as between different theories of punishment.Footnote 5 That’s the concern. But there are two ways to remain ecumenical. Either a proportionality judgement is favoured by all theories of punishment, or else it is more fundamental than those theories of punishment. I will suggest that at least one of these explanations is true of my uncontroversial case of proportionate punishment.

1 Lower Bound


Consider:

Theft: D intentionally steals £100 from C


Some punishments are obviously and uncontroversially disproportionate to the theft of £100. A death sentence is disproportionate.Footnote 6 Unfortunately, this conclusion is not very useful as a guide to real-world cases.Footnote 7 We are looking for a conclusion that is both obvious and potentially useful. Consider:

Restitution: It is not disproportionate to require D to return the £100Footnote 8

This conclusion offers modest guidance for real cases. It sets a bound that is not wholly removed from the criminal fines available in many jurisdictions.

This judgement should appeal to all stripes of punishment theorist. Restitutionary theories should be on board, for obvious reasons. Consequentialists will follow suit: insofar as any punishments serve good ends, merely stripping criminal gains must count for the incentive effects alone. (Criminals may be poorer than their victims, and so benefit from increasing marginal utility. But incentivising negative-sum transactions cannot be the best solution). Retributivists will accept that D deserves at least that much suffering. True, D may have a benign motive, or else suffered too much in other areas of life, such that depriving him of that £100 compounds his aggregately undeserved suffering. But the criminal law cannot hope to give everyone what they deserve in full generality, and it would be an implausible retributivism which demanded it.Footnote 9 Pluralists can tell the same story. Either D deserves that punishment, and it is not retributively disproportionate, or else D does not deserve that punishment, yet it is proportionate according to other dimensions of the justification of punishment.Footnote 10 If any theory of punishment disagrees, then I take that not as a mark against Restitution, but instead as a mark against such a theory. The strength of the intuition supporting Restitution is at least as strong as any intuition on which such a theory might rest.


Restitution requires that D return the stolen money. This conclusion is not frustrated if D happened to mix the stolen notes with his own notes, with no means of distinguishing the two. D must return the value of £100, not the very same notes. Nor is the conclusion frustrated if D happened to have spent (or lost) the money. He remains obliged to repay that value, even if this requires that he earn it first.Footnote 11 If we accept Restitution, then we should accept:

Compensation: It is not disproportionate to require D to repay the value of £100


We might doubt whether Compensation amounts to punishment.Footnote 12 Compensating is usually what happens before punishment kicks in. Compensation judgements justify the loss to D in part by balancing it with the gain to C. By contrast, punishment judgements focus only on the loss to D. True, many theories of punishment justify punishment in virtue of the benefits it provides to others. But most theories set certain side-constraints on the pursuit of those ends. Proportionality judgements are one such constraint. Third-party gains may be relevant to the all-things-considered permissibility or justification for punishment. But proportionality judgements are more restricted. They focus on the detriment to D and not the gain C. So, if we accept Compensation, then we should accept:

Disgorgement: It is not disproportionate to deprive D of the value of £100

Disgorgement is supported by the following cases. Imagine that C promptly dies alone and intestate, and thus cannot be compensated. This may extinguish D’s relational duty to compensate C. But it remains permissible to confiscate D’s stolen money. Or imagine that C would immediately burn the £100 once compensated. Again, the absence of gain for C does not make confiscation inapt. It is not disproportionate to deprive D of the stolen money.

Disgorgement applies to Theft. But we can generalise the conclusion in three ways. First, £100 is arbitrary. It is not disproportionate to deprive D of whatever value D stole from C. Second, per above, it makes no difference whether D retained the gain from his crime. It is clearer, then, not to talk of ‘depriving’ D of value, but rather of imposing costs on D. Third, the costs which defendants cause victims are not confined to theft. The same conclusion applies to any harms intentionally inflicted. Thus generalised, if we accept Disgorgement, then we should accept the following metric of punishment proportionality:

Lower bound: Punishment is not disproportionate if it imposes costs on D no greater than the costs which D intentionally caused to others.

2 Clarifying Lower Bound

Lower bound is a limited thesis. It is not a claim about what amount of punishment is optimal or positively proportionate. It merely states a bound at which punishment is not disproportionately severe. It applies only to crimes involving intentionally inflicted costs. It says nothing about costs which do not eventuate, nor those not intended. This is deliberate. It is controversial how exactly to weigh culpability with harm.Footnote 13 A full theory of proportionality must grapple with such cases. But I am not attempting to offer a full theory of proportionality. I focus only on the maximally uncontroversial case of legitimate punishments: punishments imposed in response to intentionally inflicted costs.Footnote 14

Even thus limited, the generalisation from Disgorgement to Lower bound faces difficulties. The cost imposed by D in Theft was denominated in money. Disgorgement used the same currency to identify a proportionate punishment. But most crimes and punishments lack this symmetry as to the kind of costs imposed. To be useful, Lower bound must offer a common currency of cost.Footnote 15

Some doubt that there can be a common currency. Gardner claims that criminal harms are incomparable with harms imposed by punishment.Footnote 16 But, if true, this implies that the (many) sentencing codes purporting to implement proportionate punishment are simply confused. Moreover, a strong version of this thesis would reject even the most obvious proportionality judgements, such as that death is disproportionate to littering.Footnote 17 That seems implausible.

How should we compare different kinds of costs? von Hirsch and Jareborg proposed that criminal harms be compared according to the degree to which those harms impact the average person’s capacity to attain certain living standards. That, in turn, was to be judged in four ranks, across four interests: physical, material, dignity, and privacy.Footnote 18 As Bagaric and McConvill fairly point out, however, this specification and categorisation of relevant interests may be idiosyncratic.Footnote 19 Bagaric and McConvill therefore proposed a more scientific common currency: happiness, as measured by empirical psychology.Footnote 20

Both proposals face a dilemma. Imagine two facts. First: their proposed harm rankings rate harm A as worse than harm B. Second: on average, people would prefer to suffer harm A rather than harm B. Here’s the dilemma. If the proposer insists that harm A is worse, then this seems mistaken. People do not prefer to suffer worse harms.Footnote 21 But if the proposer accepts that harm B is worse, then their proposed ranking is inferior to a (simpler) preference-based ranking.Footnote 22Preferences offer the most straightforward way to compare different kinds of cost. The lesser cost between a £100 fine and a day in prison is simply whatever D would prefer.

Still: whose preferences? Imagine that D intentionally breaks C’s nose. C may value her nose not being broken at £100. By contrast, D might value his nose at £1000. Which is the relevant metric? A related difficulty is often raised as an objection to retributive theories of proportionality. On retributive theories, deserved suffering is the common currency of punishment severity.Footnote 23 But ensuring that equal suffering is imposed for equal crimes leads to a dilemma. Equal sentences may produce differential suffering. A small prison cell makes Tall suffer more than Short. That is objectionable. On the other hand, equal suffering may require differential sentences. As Socialite suffers more from imprisonment than Hermit, it follows that Hermit requires a much longer sentence to be caused equal suffering. That too is objectionable. We reach an impasse.Footnote 24 Some reject retributive theories of proportionality for this reason.Footnote 25 And these objections seemingly apply with equal force to my claim that we should weigh the costs of crime and punishments according to preferences, for preferences are no less variable than propensity to suffer.

The standard solution to this dilemma is to standardise. We focus on average suffering, average living standards, average happiness, or average preferences.Footnote 26 Ryberg points out that standardising is a distinctly second-rate solution for retributivists. They want to proportion punishment severity to the particular defendant’s desert, not the average defendant’s desert.Footnote 27 But there is simply no alternative but to standardise.Footnote 28 I suggested above that what D deserves to suffer will depend on the severity of his crime, and the severity of his crime will in part depend on the costs he caused to others. Regardless of the metric chosen, there is no way to compare costs to C against costs to D without standardisation. But this is not unique to counting costs, nor to a preference-based currency. The infinite variety of pre-legal wrongs are standardised by crime definitions: theft, robbery, murder, and so on. Every shade of culpability is standardised by mens rea categories: intent, recklessness, negligence, and so on. It should come as no surprise, and offer no objection, that the same holds when it comes to identifying the costs of crime.Footnote 29 We should consider average preferences. This does not entail that the idiosyncratic costs to particular victims are irrelevant. The best way to implement this standardisation may be to set the average costs of that type of crime as a starting point, but to allow further evidence as to any deviations in a particular case. If D harms C knowing that C will be harmed more than the average victim, then D intends that additional harm to C, and Lower bound says that more-than-average punishment is not disproportionate.Footnote 30 But, absent that information, we must settle for the average costs of that type of crime. The same is true in principle for punishments, though there are powerful reasons to resist accounting for D’s characteristics.Footnote 31

This suggests a (mostly) objective currency of cost. That should be unsurprising, for we have already seen such a metric in action. Restitution said that D must return the stolen £100. That applied regardless of whether D was rich or poor. It may be that D, being poor, suffers greatly from losing that £100. Perhaps much more than C suffered in losing it. Still, it seems clear that depriving D of that money is not disproportionate. As such, at least some proportionality judgements sound in an objective metric. It does not follow that it is impermissible to make the rich pay more. But Restitution does set an objective floor of permissible punishment.

I have suggested that preferences offer the most parsimonious metric with which to measure the costs of crime and punishment. This also allows us to draw on the deep economic literature which attempts to measure those costs. This is not to say that measuring these costs is easy. It is not. Preferences may be inchoate and subject to revision. They may be means-ends irrational. Stated preferences may differ from revealed preferences. Different measurement strategies may come to different estimates as to the costs of crime. But the complexity of preferences and their identification reflects the complexities of the subject matter. We should not expect that comparing the very different and very subtle costs of crimes and punishments would be easy. I can offer no expertise in identifying these costs. But, in the next section, I will suggest which categories of costs we ought to consider.

3 The Costs of Crime

Lower bound says that punishment is not disproportionate if it imposes costs on D no greater than the costs which D intentionally caused to others. This requires that we know (1) what costs D caused, and (2) of those, which D intended. This section addresses (1).

My claim is that we undercount the costs of crime. Most writing on proportionality focuses on the direct cost of crime. In Theft, that was £100. But this is far from the whole cost. Sometimes the marginal cost is noted. D caused C not just the loss of £100, but also anguish. And not just to C, but most likely her loved ones too.Footnote 32 D caused various criminal justice costs: the costs of police, prosecutors, lawyers, judges; their administrators, buildings, equipment, and travel. These are sometimes, if not always, recognised. But very rarely mentioned is the average cost of crime.Footnote 33 Many people take precautionary measures against being victimised, measures like taking taxis and buying security devices. These costs are not taken in response to any one criminal, but instead in response to all crime of some type. D causally contributes to the need to take such precautions, and hence to the total cost of crime. Finally, we should count not just out-of-pocket costs, but also opportunity costs, like the foregone value of walks at night. Together, these costs will far exceed the £100 stolen. Focusing on direct costs strongly undercounts the costs of crime.


To get a feel for these costs, consider two cases:

City: In a city, D1 steals C’s bike. The police inform C that nothing can be done. The total cost of D1’s theft sums to £100.

Village: In a village, nobody locks up their bikes. D2 moves into the village and steals one bike. This causes all the villagers change their habits and buy locks. The total costs of D2’s theft sum to £10,000.

Both Ds commit the same crime. In Village, we can see the full costs imposed by D’s crime. A single thief can force a change of routine for an entire community. In City, however, those costs are masked. Regardless of D1’s conduct, the City folk would have raised their defences to other potential thieves.


Now, it would not be fair to hold D1 responsible for the actions of those other thieves. As von Hirsch and Jareborg put it,

Because a burglar is responsible only for his conduct, it is the harm that his conduct causes...that determines the gravity of the offence (not the totality of harm caused by the acts of all burglars, over whom he has no control).Footnote 34

But it would be fair to hold D1 responsible for his share of the total cost caused. Imagine that City has five bike thieves operating in the area, and, per Village, the threat they pose to bike security forces residents to take costly precautions summing to £10,000. If each steals a bike, they together cause £500 of marginal costs. Together, however, they cause an additional £9500 in precautionary costs. This outcome is overdetermined. But that is no bar to finding causal responsibility. Assuming equal causal responsibility, we may fairly attribute to them their share of the total cost: £2000.Footnote 35 That is, we may attribute to them the average cost of that type of crime.Footnote 36

My claim is that the focusing on the marginal cost strongly undercounts the average cost of crime. This is borne out by empirical work. A recent paper for the British Home Office estimated various costs of crime. The authors distinguish consequential costs from costs incurred in anticipation of and response to crime. Consequential costs are a reasonable proxy for marginal costs, while anticipation and response costs would be included within the average cost of crime.Footnote 37 They estimate that, on average, the consequential cost of vehicle theft is £4670. But the total cost, including anticipation and response measures, exceeds £10,000. For arson, the consequences sum to £3000, but the total cost exceeds £8000.Footnote 38 The total unit (average) cost significantly exceeds the consequential (marginal) cost.

Cost of crime estimates face formidable epistemic challenges. The Home Office paper tried to estimate the costs of each crime type in a ‘bottom-up’ way: identifying various costs incurred due to victimisation, prevention, and in response to crime. For example, they estimate the total expenditure on dedicated security products like burglar alarms, then divide that by the estimated number of burglaries. But this does not count, for example, the expenditure on products purchased in part for security against crime, like SUVs or taxi services. Nor does it account for the opportunity costs of crime: valuable foregone opportunities.

There are ways to estimate these costs. Researchers can ask people how much they are willing to pay to avoid victimisation. More creatively, they can use proxies like house prices to reveal implicit willingness to pay to avoid local crime. These ‘top-down’ methods often produce estimates between 2 and 5 times greater than ‘bottom-up’ methods.Footnote 39 Consider an example. The Home Office paper estimated the unit cost of domestic burglary as just under £6000. Of this, they noted that household expenditure defending against burglary (eg burglar alarms) cost £320 per burglary.Footnote 40 I expect that the average household would happily pay at least this amount to guarantee not being burgled. If I’m right, the real cost of burglary is more like £320 per household. And this implies that the true average cost per burglary is closer to £11,000.Footnote 41 Using the average cost rather than the marginal cost massively increases the Lower bound of proportionate punishment.

Even the most sophisticated causal identification strategies cannot measure the full opportunity costs of crime. That requires not just constructing clever proxies, but also imagining alternative possible worlds. Some opportunity costs are easy to imagine because they were absent in the past. For example, the cost of airport security checks. (Quick estimate: at least $22bn per year in the US alone).Footnote 42 Other opportunity costs are easy to imagine because they’ve only recently been mitigated. Until recently, it was nigh unthinkable to transact at arms-length with, pay for chauffeuring from, or stay in the home of individual strangers. The unthinkable is now routine, thanks to PayPal, Uber, Airbnb, and other platforms. A major component of the success of these companies lay in assuring people that they would not be scammed or murdered.Footnote 43 There was never any insuperable barrier to mail-order transacting or paying strangers for a lift or a room. But would-be scammers and murderers prevented that value from being realised, until these companies could resolve the assurance problem. Their multi-billion valuations and massive consumer surplus are an indicium of the previously-unrealised opportunity cost of such crimes.

A good statistician may be able to estimate the crime-avoiding component of the value such companies generate. But no statistician can measure the value of the companies which have not been created, or the rewards to be reaped from solving remaining assurance problems. The hardest opportunity costs to imagine are those we have always and still do suffer. They go unthought. But they are no less costs of crime, and quite possibly the largest component of that cost. Almost every crime contributes, in some way, to causing these opportunity costs.

Estimating a particular defendant’s contribution to causing these (already hard-to-estimate) costs will be extremely difficult. We must work out the number of offenders, and whether their crime was more or less costly than average. We will have to disaggregate the combined effect of different crime types, such as murder and robbery, to work out their relative contribution to the cost of (say) fear and precautions against violence. And we will have to work out the temporal and spatial extent of these causal contributions. In practice, these will be very rough estimates, subject to more detailed evidence. Lower bound cannot offer precision.

A defendant may claim that these costs are too causally remote from their crime. But, with a little imagination, these costs are certainly foreseeable. That meets the usual lawyer’s test for causal proximity. Alternatively, D may claim that many of these costs are incurred via the free and deliberate actions of others, actions often said to break the causal chain between D and further consequences. But this rule does not apply to officials reasonably responding to crime, nor to reasonable reactions by victims.Footnote 44 All of the costs I have mentioned plausibly fall into those categories. It seems fair to hold defendants causally responsible for their contribution to all of these costs of crime.

4 Culpable Costs

I have suggested, however roughly, how we might measure the costs of crime. Lower bound then asks us to consider which of those costs D intended.

No defendant sets out to cause all of the costs mentioned above. But we do not only intend our ultimate ends. In law, we are said to (indirectly) intend any known consequences of our intentional actions.Footnote 45 In Theft, D does not intend to cause harm of merely £100. He also knows, and so intends, to cause C to suffer further consequences. If D knew of his entire contribution to the average cost of that type of crime, then Lower bound says that punishments which match those costs are not disproportionate.Footnote 46

In practice, it will be hard to prove exactly what D knows. But a legal system could quite easily advertise the average cost of various types of crime, and thereby make it the case that defendants must know, and so intend, to cause those costs when offending. (Indeed, a sentencing scale partly fulfils this function by signalling the severity of each crime).

Because Lower bound is intended to be maximally uncontroversial, I limited its scope to intention and knowledge. But it could be modified to weaken that assumption and to stretch to recklessly caused costs. That modified version of Lower bound would make it easier yet to attribute to D the average cost of that type of crime.

5 What Follows?

If the costs of crime are usually undercounted, then Lower bound, which indexes to those costs, may bless as proportionate some punishments which are intuitively quite severe. The Home Office paper suggests that the average personal theft is of goods valued at £180. For this, we may intuitively think that anything much worse than a small fine would be too harsh. English sentencing law agrees. For petty theft below £500, without threatening the victim, offenders are fined 125% to 175% of their weekly income (and must disgorge any additional value of the stolen goods).Footnote 47 Assuming that the average petty thief earns about half the UK average (so, £250) that is a range of roughly £310 to £440.Footnote 48 But the Home Office report estimates the full average cost of theft as £1380. And, given that this is an underestimate, the total cost may easily be several times higher. Lower bound would therefore accept fines many times higher than at current levels.

Of course, as I have emphasised throughout, Lower bound does not attempt to offer a full theory of proportionality, still less a full theory of permissible punishment. There may be many excellent reasons why fines of that level are a bad idea. Most obviously, many criminals simply cannot pay them.Footnote 49 (Indeed, more serious offences quickly result in incarceration as a result). Even if defendants could pay such amounts, there may be good moral and prudential reasons not to further immiserate poor criminals. But Lower bound does help us to structure our thinking here. Such objections to more severe sentences should not sound as claims about disproportionality. Rather, they should sound as claims about the instrumental costs and benefits of different punishment regimes.