Skip to main content
Log in

Politics and Metaphysics in Plato and Al-Fārābī: Distinguishing the Virtuous City of Al-Fārābī from that of Plato in Terms of their Distinct Metaphysics

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Mabādi’ ārā’ ahl al-madīna al-fādila as well as other major political writings of al-Fārābī, politics is accompanied by metaphysics. However, the co-existence of politics and Neoplatonic metaphysics in al-Fārābī is usually refuted on the basis of two major arguments: one, the Neoplatonic argument, which denies al-Fārābī’s politics; and two, the Straussian argument, which denies al-Fārābī’s Neoplatonic metaphysics. However, this article would show that the two arguments against the co-existence of politics and Neoplatonic metaphysics in al-Fārābī are faulty, and that politics and Neoplatonic metaphysics certainly co-exist in al-Fārābī’s philosophical thought. It would be shown that, in fact, Neoplatonic metaphysics plays an important role in al-Fārābī’s politics and distinguishes his theory of the virtuous city from that of Plato’s Republic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mabādi’ ārā’ ahl al-madīna al-fādila is hereafter referred to as Ārā’.

  2. Leo Strauss and his followers argue against the Neoplatonic metaphysics of al-Fārābī. They do not recognize al-Fārābī’s Neoplatonic metaphysics as a genuine part of his philosophical thought. They suggest that al-Fārābī’s Neoplatonic metaphysics is exoteric, a mere tool to make his controversial views palatable to the religious section of his society. I would discuss this Straussian argument against the Neoplatonic metaphysics of al-Fārābī in Section 4.1.2 of the article. Furthermore, I would provide a counter-argument against the Straussian argument in Section 4.2.2, and would show that the Straussian argument is based on unsound grounds.

  3. For al-Fārābī’s detailed characterization of the First Being see Al-Fārābī 1985, pp. 57–89.

  4. Strauss and his followers give the same argument for medieval Muslim philosophers’ preference for Plato’s Republic over Aristotle’s Politics in their political discussions. They argue that medieval Muslim philosophers worked in a hostile environment and were compelled to present their views in conformity with the Islamic religion. Since Plato’s Republic suits Islamic theological views and Aristotle’s Politics does not, Medieval Muslim philosophers based their political discussions on Plato’s Republic and not on Aristotle’s Politics. However, in my recent article, I (Ali, 2022) have refuted this argument, and have suggested an alternative reason for medieval Muslim philosophers’ preference for Plato’s Republic in their political discussions. For details see Ali 2022.

  5. For a detailed discussion on the relationship between the virtuous city of al-Fārābī and the first Muslim polity see Ali and Qin (2019).

References

  • Al-Fārābī,. (1985). Mabādi’ ārā’ ahl al-madīna al-fādila. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ali, I. (2022). On the transmission of Greek philosophy to medieval Muslim philosophers. HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies, 78(4), 1–8. https://doi.org/10.4102/hts.v78i4.7504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ali, I., & Mingli, Q. (2019). Distinguishing the virtuous city of Alfarabi from that of Plato in light of his unique historical context. HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies, 75(4), 907–915. https://doi.org/10.4102/hts.v75i4.5370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ali, I., & Qin, M. (2020). City and soul in Plato and Alfarabi: An explanation for the differences between Plato’s and Alfarabi’s theory of city in terms of their distinct psychology. Axiomathes, 30(1), 91–105. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09439-w

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, H. (1978). 529 and its sequel: What happened to the academy? Byzantion, 48(2), 369–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodeus, R. (2000). Aristote et la theologie des vivants immortels. Translated by J. Garrett as Aristotle and the theology of the living immortals. State University of New York Press, New York

  • Bordt, M. (2006). Platons Theologie. Verlag Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Britannica, T. E. E. (1998). Emanationism. In: Encyclopedia Britannica. https://www.britannica.com/topic/emanationism. Cited 11 Jul 2021

  • Butterworth, C. E. (1972). Rhetoric and Islamic political philosophy. International Journal of Middle East Studies, 3(2), 187–198. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020743800024879

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, A. (1969). The last days of the academy at Athens. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, 15(195), 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Catana, L. (2013). The origin of the division between middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. Apeiron, 46(2), 166–200. https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2012-0029

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corbin, H. (1993). History of Islamic philosophy. Translated by Liadain Sherrard & Philip Sherrard. Kegan Paul International Limited, London

  • De Vogel, C. J. (1970). What was god for Plato? In: Philosophia: studies in Greek philosophy.  (pp 210–242). Van Gorcum, Assen

  • Enders, M. (1999). Platons theologie: Der gott, die gotter und das gute. Perspektiven Der Philosophie, 25, 131–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fakhry, M. (2002). Al-Fārābi, founder of Islamic Neoplatonism: His life, works and influence. Oneworld Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festugiere A (1936) Contemplation et vie contemplative selon Platon. Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, Paris

  • Friedlander, P. (1928). Platon (Vol. 1). Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerostergios, A. (1982). Justinian the great, the emperor and saint: illustrious Byzantine emperor, legislator, and codifier of law. Institute for Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies, Belmont, Massachusetts

  • Gutas, D. (2002). The study of Arabic philosophy in the twentieth century: An essay on the historiography of Arabic philosophy. British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies, 29(1), 5–25. https://doi.org/10.1080/13530190220124043

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karfik, F. (2004). Die beseelung des kosmos: untersuchungen zur kosmologie, seelenlehre und theologie in Platons Phaidon und Timaios. K.G. Saur, Munich and Leipzig

  • Kramer, H. J. (1959). Arete bei Platon und Aristoteles: Zum wesen und zur geschichte der platonischen ontologie. Winter Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahdi, M. S. (2001). Alfarabi and the foundation of Islamic political philosophy. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyerhof, M. (1948). Alī al-Bayhaqī’s tatimmat siwān al-Hikma: A biographical work on learned men of the Islam. Osiris, 8, 122–217. https://doi.org/10.1086/368514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Meara, D. (2005). Platonopolis: Platonic political philosophy in late antiquity. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parens, J. (1995). Metaphysics as rhetoric: Alfarabi’s summary of Plato’s Laws. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riel, G. V. (2016). Plato’s gods. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ritter, C. (1923). Platon, vol 2. Beck, Munich

  • Robin, L. (1968). Platon (2nd ed.). Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, A. (2014). Plato’s middle period metaphysics and epistemology. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/plato-metaphysics. Cited 19 Sept 2021

  • Strauss, L. (1989). How to begin to study medieval philosophy. In T. L. Pangle (Ed.), The rebirth of classical political rationalism: An introduction to the thought of Leo Strauss (pp. 207–226). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. (1945). Farabi’s Plato. Louis Ginzberg: Jubilee volume on the occasion of his seventieth birthday (pp. 357–393). American Academy for Jewish Research

  • Verdenius, W. J. (1954). Platons Gottesbegriff. In Entretiens sur l’antiquite classique: la notion du divin depuis Homère jusqu’à Platon (pp. 241–283). Fondation Hardt, Geneva

  • Watts, E. (2004). Justinian, Malalas, and the end of Athenian philosophical teaching in A.D. 529. The Journal of Roman Studies, 94, 168–182. https://doi.org/10.2307/4135014

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, T. (1918). The Neoplatonists: A study in the history of Hellenism (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. V. (1920). Platon. Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ishraq Ali.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author has no conflict of interest to disclose, financial or otherwise.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This research was supported by the China Postdoctoral Science Foundation Fund project, “Philosophy vs Theology: Research on Medieval Arab Thought From a Historical Perspective” (2022M712803).

This research was also supported by the National Social Science Fund of China project, “Research on the Tradition of the Theory of Creation” (20BZJ032).

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ali, I. Politics and Metaphysics in Plato and Al-Fārābī: Distinguishing the Virtuous City of Al-Fārābī from that of Plato in Terms of their Distinct Metaphysics. Philosophia 51, 1041–1061 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-022-00597-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-022-00597-7

Keywords

Navigation