Skip to main content
Log in

Propositional Intentionalism and the Argument from Appearance

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The argument from appearance for the content view or intentionalism attracts a lot of attention recently. In my paper, I follow Charles Travis to argue against the key premise that representational content can be ‘read off’ from a certain way that a thing looks to a subject. My arguments are built upon Travis’s original objection and a reinterpretation of Rodrick Chisholm’s comparative and noncomparative uses of appearance words. Byrne, Schellenberg and others interpret Travis’ ‘visual looks’ as Chisholm’s comparative use, and appeal to the noncomparative use as an alternative to avoid Travis’s objection. I demonstrate that they misunderstand both Chisholm and Travis. Both the comparative use and the noncomparative use are semantic notions, while ‘visual looks’ is a metaphysical one. Although Chisholm’s appearance objectivism –– that appearance expressions attribute appearances to ordinary objects –– is close to ‘visual looks’, appearance objectivism is not exceptional to the noncomparative use as Byrne interprets. In the end, I also show that Byrnean’s conception of distinctive visual gestalt cannot exclude contrary representational contents, because a distinctive visual gestalt can be shared by different kinds of things. Besides, Byrne and others do not explain why a distinctive visual gestalt should be presented as ‘being instantiated’. Therefore, I conclude that representational content cannot be read off from a certain way that a thing looks to a subject; the argument from appearance thus fails.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Intentionalists include Searle (1983); Harman (1990); Dretske (1995); Tye (1995); Byrne (2001, (2009; Siegel, (2010a, b; Schellenberg, (2011); Brogaard (2015, (2017), etc. In this paper, I do not make a distinction among intentionalism, representationalism, and the content view.

  2. A similar view is shared by Brewer (2006, p.174).

  3. Most intentionalists are propositional intentionalists, such as Searle (1983), Dretske (1995), Tye (1995), Byrne (2001), etc.

  4. For the detailed and more lucid discussion about the notion of availability, see Wilson (2018).

  5. Similar summaries of Travis’s argument can be seen in Byrne (2009), Schellenberg (2011), Brogaard (2017), Wilson (2018).

  6. For the discussion about epistemic use, see Jackson (1977), Martin (2010), Brogaard (2015), Glüer (2017).

  7. Briefly, Jackson argues that material things do not have color properties because color properties do not serve any scientific causal explanation of the interactions between objects, while sense-data as the immediate perceptual objects have color properties. Hence, sense-data are not material but mental. See Jackson (1977, pp. 120–28).

  8. Jackson’s detailed argument for the independence of the phenomenal use can be seen in (1977, pp. 34 − 6). For the objection, see Martin (2010, p. 180-1).

  9. See Jackson (1982).

  10. Wilson (2018) has a more detailed analysis on Travis’s view on looks.

  11. I am suspicious that Travis’s objection relies on a subject’s epistemic state as Brogaard thinks. As I propose, Travis’s visual looks are objective. Raleigh (2013a, b; Wilson, (2018)) also do not think that visual looks are dependent on epistemic states.

  12. I thank one referee for posing this challenge.

  13. Brogaard (2017) has a more detailed discussion of dual looks.

References

  • Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(2), 165–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2008). How to account for illusion. In A. Haddock, & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge (pp. 168–180). Oxford University Press

  • Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and Its Objects. Oxford University Press

  • Brogaard, B. (2015). Perceptual Reports. In Mohan Matthen (ed.), Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. Oxford University Press

  • Brogaard, B. (2017). Perception Without Representation? On Travis’s Argument Against the Representational View of Perception. Topoi, 36(2), 273–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review, 110(2), 199–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2009). Experience and content. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 429–451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1957). Perceiving: A Philosophical Study (9 vol.). Cornell University Press

  • Crane, T. (2009). Is Perception a Propositional Attitude? Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 452–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2013). The Given. Joseph Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason and Being-in the-World: the McDowell-Dreyfus Debate (pp. 229–249). London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. MIT Press

  • Glüer, K. (2017). Talking about Looks. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(4), 781–807

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ivanov, I. (2017). Property-awareness and representation. Topoi, 36(2), 331–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A Representative Theory. Cambridge University Press

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32(April), 127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raleigh, T. (2013a). Phenomenology without Representation. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(3), 1209–1237

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2010). What’s in a look?. In Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World (pp. 160–225). Oxford University Press

  • Noë, A. (2005). Action in Perception. MIT Press

  • Pautz, A. (2009). What are the contents of experiences. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 483–507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition?: The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–365

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raleigh, T. (2013b). Phenomenology without Representation. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(3), 1209–1237

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2011).Perceptual Content Defended. Noûs, 45(4),714–750

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Subject and object in the contents of visual experience. Philosophical Review, 115(3), 355–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2010a). Do visual experiences have contents? In Bence -Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World. Oxford University Press

  • Siegel, S. (2010b). The Contents of Visual Experience. Oxford University Press USA

  • Thau, M. (2002). Consciousness and Cognition: Unified Account. Oxford University Press

  • Travis, C. (2004). The silence of the senses. Mind, 113(449), 57–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2013). Perception: Essays After Frege. Oxford University Press

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. MIT Press

  • Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Noûs, 36(1), 137–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, K. A. (2018). Are the Senses Silent? Travis’s Argument from Looks. In John Collins, & T. Dobler (Eds.), The Philosophy of Charles Travis: Language, Thought, and Perception (pp. 199–221). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article was written when I was a graduate student at CEU. Its earlier version was presented at the Copenhagen Summer School in Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, and I am indebted to discussions with audiences there, especially Søren Overgaard. I’m also grateful to Keith Allen, Tim Crane, Damian Aleksiev, and Hanoch Ben-Yami for their valuable comments on the article’s various earlier versions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zhiwei Gu.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gu, Z. Propositional Intentionalism and the Argument from Appearance. Philosophia 51, 697–715 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-022-00575-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-022-00575-z

Keywords

Navigation