Skip to main content
Log in

Abundance and Variety in Nature: Fact and Value

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The mass extinction visited upon us by capitalism involves many kinds of devastation. Here I clarify the grounds for assessing the most obvious of these harms, i.e., decimation of species diversity. The thesis that variety among species has intrinsic value motivates, and in turn follows from, the “variable value view” (VVV) of abundance within any given species. In contrast, standard axiologies have no place for the intrinsic value of species diversity. I show that the VVV provides a better justification than the latter do, of the way in which a widely-used empirical indicator summarizes the overall state of life on Earth. These considerations favor ecocentric value theory – which ascribes intrinsic value to properties of ecological wholes, like species diversity, that do not supervene on the well-being of their constituent organisms – over its main competitors. I conclude by widening the focus from wild nature alone to the biosphere comprising both wilderness and the domesticated realm. This broadened perspective helps to link the science and ethics of biodiversity with the political struggle to extract ourselves from the moral abyss of mass extinction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout this paper, I use “well-being” and “welfare” to denote whatever it is that makes individual lives intrinsically valuable. I also assume positive average well-being. If average well-being were negative for a particular case, the claims to follow could be adjusted accordingly. On the implausibility of negative averages for nature in general, see Mikkelson (2018).

  2. See van Dooren (2014) for a moving account of how differently particular individual birds have actually fared during the effort to save the whooping crane species.

  3. Conversely, if coot numbers had increased by 34 while whooping cranes went extinct, the AP and TP would again register no gain or loss, whereas the VVV would entail a loss. See Odenbaugh (in review) for an actual example of a common species expanding at the expense of a related, endangered (sub-) species.

  4. This implication is analogous to prioritarianism’s implication that equality of well-being among individuals within a species has intrinsic value. In other words, “prioritarianism is a sort of egalitarianism” (Gosepath, 2021).

  5. The proposition, that species diversity has intrinsic value not reducible to the intrinsic value (e.g., well-being) of individual organisms, is distinct from the proposition that individual species, considered separately, have such value. Bradley (2001) rebutted several arguments for the latter proposition, and defended the former. I have not examined whether Bradley’s rebuttals also apply to Smith’s (2016) later argument for the irreducible intrinsic value of species.

  6. Here I use base-10 logarithms, but could have used any other base, since it makes no difference to the final estimate. For the sake of simplicity I use the raw abundances, whereas the WWF uses more complex methods to estimate yearly changes within each population (McRae et al., 2017).

  7. It is already weighted for differences in research effort across taxa and locations. In principle, the LPI could also be weighted according to other criteria, such as the evolutionary distinctiveness of different species (cf. Palmer & Fischer, 2021).

  8. Individual well-being should not be ignored at finer scales, where decisions about how to conserve particular species have significant impacts on particular non-human persons as well as human cultural attitudes (Wallach et al., 2020).

  9. This seems to be a particular instance of a more general problem, i.e., anthropocentrism in practice despite non-anthropocentrism in principle. For another example, see McShane’s (2016) critique of climate ethics and policy for instantiating this same problem.

  10. For example, in Mikkelson (2011) I link RT to deep ecology and the work of Rolston (1981), and in Mikkelson (2019) I link it to Leopold’s land ethic.

  11. Kelly (2014) makes an interesting case that richness does explain those two values in particular – not to mention his heroic argument that it underlies all value in general. See Crist (in review) on the importance of freedom for understanding and counteracting mass extinction.

  12. See Washington et al. (2018) on the continuing importance of ecocentrism for conservation biology.

  13. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  14. Similarly – as Hurka (1983) already pointed out – the VVV does better than the average principle (AP) does in the face of the classic objection to the latter. While the AP always violates the so-called mere addition principle, the VVV does not always violate it.

  15. This will not be the case when growth slows down for good, to below the economy’s rate of improvement in ecological efficiency – a point that will roughly coincide with the end of capitalism (Mikkelson 2017, 2021).

  16. See Preston (2021) on difficulties in defining just when that final point has been reached.

  17. Thanks to Cafaro (2017) for the notion that mass extinction is a moral abyss, and d'Arcy (2014) for the term “plutogenic” as an alternative to “anthropogenic”.

References

  • Almond, R. E. A., Grooten, M., & Petersen, T. (Eds.). (2020). Living planet report 2020: Bending the curve of biodiversity loss. Worldwide Fund for Nature. Gland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby, C., & Donaldson, D. (1984). Social criteria for evaluating population change. Journal of Public Economics, 25, 13–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2001). The value of endangered species. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 35, 43–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradshaw, C. J. A., Ehrlich, P. R., Beattie, A., et al. (2021). Underestimating the challenges of avoiding a ghastly future. Frontiers in Conservation Science, 1, 615419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cafaro, P. (2017). Valuing wild nature. In S. M. Gardiner & A. Thompson (Eds.), Oxford handbook of environmental ethics (pp. 125–138). Oxford University. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cafaro, P. (In review). Climate ethics and population policy: A review of recent work.

  • Canadian Wildlife Service. (2010). COSEWIC assessment and status report on the whooping Crane Grus Americana in Canada. Committee on the status of endangered wildlife in Canada. Ottawa, .

  • Crist, E. (In review). Witnessing mass extinction: What's invisible, what's visible, what's possible.

  • d'Arcy, S. (2014). Environmentalism as if winning mattered: A self-organization strategy. The public autonomy project September 17th.

  • Drenthen, M. (In review). Bears and apple trees: Coexisting with wildlife in cultural landscapes.

  • Gosepath, S. (2021). Equality. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/equality.

  • Greaves, H. (2017). Population axiology. Philosophy Compass, 12, e12442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hickel, J. (2020). Less is more: How degrowth will save the world. William Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1983). Value and population size. Ethics, 93, 496–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2011). The best things in life: A guide to what really matters. Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, C. (2014). Value monism, richness, and environmental ethics. Les ateliers de l’éthique/The Ethics Forum, 9, 110–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, D. (1976). Empirical disconfirmation and ethical counter-example. Journal of Value Inquiry, 10, 30–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, A. (1949). A Sand County almanac. Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • McRae, L., Deinet, S., & Freeman, R. (2017). The diversity-weighted living planet index: Controlling for taxonomic bias in a global biodiversity indicator. Public Library of Science ONE, 12, e0169156.

    Google Scholar 

  • McShane, K. (2016). Anthropocentrism in climate ethics and policy. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 40, 189–204.

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2011). Weighing species. Environmental Ethics, 33, 185–196.

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2017). Environmental values, human nature, and economic democracy. Human Ecology, 45, 131–134.

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2018). Convergence and divergence between ecocentrism and sentientism concerning net value. Les ateliers de l'éthique, 13(1), 101–114.

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2019). Sentience, life, richness. In DesRoches, C. T., F. Jankunis, & B. Williston (Eds.), Canadian environmental philosophy (pp. 83–96). McGill-Queens.

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2021). Invisible hand or ecological footprint? Comparing social versus environmental impacts of recent economic growth. Organization and Environment, 34, 287–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelson, G. M. & C. A. Chapman. (2014). Individualistic environmental ethics: A reductio ad exstinctum? Environmental Ethics, 36, 333–338.

  • Miller, P. (1983). Axiology: A metaphysical theme in ethics. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 17, 3–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, P. (1995). Integrity, sustainability, biodiversity, and forestry. In L. Westra & J. Lemons (Eds.), Perspectives on ecological integrity (pp. 218–238). Kluwer. Amsterdam.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Naess, A. (1986). Intrinsic value: Will the defenders of nature please rise? In M. E. Soulé (Ed.), Conservation biology: The science of scarcity and diversity (pp. 504–515). Sinauer Associates. Sunderland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nikolaeva, E. I. (2010). A monitoring program for the Amur Tiger: Thirteenth-year report 1998–2010. Wildlife Conservation Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (In review). Owls and old-growth: An examination of the multi-layered moral conflicts.

  • Palmer, C. & B. Fischer. 2021. Should global conservation initiatives prioritize phylogenetic diversity? Philosophia (online first articles).

  • Preston, C. L. 2021. Extinct and alive: Towards a broader account of loss. Philosophia (online first articles).

  • Rolston III, H. (1981). Values in nature. Environmental Ethics, 3, 113–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. L. (In review). Species extinction, mass extinction, and ethical theory.

  • Singer, P. (1980). Practical ethics. Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, I. A. (2016). The intrinsic value of endangered species. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E. (1985). What is conservation biology? BioScience, 35, 727–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E. (1987). History of the Society for Conservation Biology: How and why we got here. Conservation Biology, 1, 4–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, P. W. (1981). The ethics of respect for nature. Environmental Ethics, 3, 197–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tilman, D. (2000). Causes, consequences and ethics of biodiversity. Nature, 405, 208–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service. (2005). Recovery of nationally endangered wildlife. U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dooren, T. (2014). Flight ways: Life and loss at the edge of extinction. Columbia University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallach, A. D., Batavia, C., Bekoff, M., et al. (2020). Recognizing animal personhood in compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 34, 1097–1106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Washington, H., Chapron, G., Kopnina, H., et al. (2018). Foregrounding ecojustice in conservation. Biological Conservation, 228, 367–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wikipedia. (2021). Eddington number. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Eddington_number.

Download references

Acknowledgments

For feedback on this paper, thanks to Ron Sandler, Phil Cafaro, and other fellow participants in the workshop leading to its submission; as well as Jeremy Bendik-Keymer, and three anonymous reviewers.

Funding

Thanks to Phil Cafaro and Ron Sandler for funding my participation in the workshop leading to submission of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregory M. Mikkelson.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mikkelson, G.M. Abundance and Variety in Nature: Fact and Value. Philosophia 50, 2235–2247 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00451-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00451-2

Keywords

Navigation