1 Introduction

Modal dispositionalism (MD) semantically reduces, and ontologically explicates, possibility and necessity in terms of dispositionality. For MD, the dispositions of actual objects are taken as the truth-makers of modal claims.Footnote 1 So, (roughly) some object’s having the disposition to bring it about that p makes-true the modal claim <possibly: p >.

Borghini and Williams’s (2008) version of MD (‘MD’ shall refer exclusively to their theory) is the chief dispositionalist theory of concern here – however some of the points I raise generalize to other modal dispositionalist theories.Footnote 2 The roadmap for this paper is the following: Section 2 sets up MD’s ontology by explaining what dispositions and dispositional properties are, and provides an exposition of MD; and, section 3 examines an instance of MD’s formal deficiency – specifically, I examine Yates’s (2015) objection that, in the case of certain actualized necessities, modal dispositionalism’s biconditionals for possibility and necessity invalidate the (T)-axiom, and I apply this objection to MD. To Yates’s objection, I assess the two most plausible responses – one of which is owed to Yates (which is also provided in his (2015)), and the other to Allen (2017). I argue that both responses fail to save MD: crucially, they ignore critical aspects of MD.Footnote 3 Indeed, Yates’s response requires one to ignore MD’s universal dispositionalist aim insofar as his response threatens to render dispositions redundant in MD’s explication of modality, and Allen’s response requires one either to ignore MD’s naturalism or to accept that MD is – at best – ontologically bizarre or – at worst – absurd. I conclude that neither of the two most plausible responses to Yates’s objection are successful. Thus, MD should be rejected – whilst some modal logical axioms may be negotiable, some are not; certainly (T) is not.

2 Dispositions, Dispositional Properties and MD

Let us Get a Grip on MD’s Ontology. Dispositions, when under suitable stimulus conditions,Footnote 4 manifest, and thereby produce or bring about certain states of affairs.Footnote 5 That is to say, dispositions are considered abilities of objects to produce certain states of affairs, and so, standardly, dispositionality is understood in modal terms.Footnote 6 Furthermore, (at least some) dispositions can manifest under multiple different stimulus conditions: for instance, a teacup will shatter if it is thrown against a hard surface – but, a teacup will also shatter if it is knocked with a mallet. Moreover, it is conventional for dispositions to be characterized by their manifestation-types – so, objects have dispositions for certain manifestations: for instance, a teacup’s fragile disposition is characterised by its manifestation being such that, under the appropriate stimulus conditions, the teacup shatters. And so, a teacup’s being fragile constitutes a disposition for shattering. Herein, I follow the above conventions.

The view that objects have dispositions through having certain properties is called dispositional realism.Footnote 7 Central to dispositional realism is the notion that objects may possess dispositions that may never manifest. Thus, objects do not have certain dispositions because of the properties they had or will have, but instead because of the properties that they currently have. Importantly, there are two factions amongst the realists: the reductivists and the non-reductivists (/essentialists). Reductivists contend: the properties that ground dispositions are essentially non-dispositional (or categorical) – viz., non-dispositional properties ground dispositions and their manifestations.Footnote 8 Non-reductivists, however, contend: essentially, irreducibly dispositional properties ground dispositions and their manifestations.Footnote 9 So, essentially dispositional properties essentially dispose their object-bearers to behave in particular ways.

Now, Borghini and Williams (2008) are in the non-reductivist camp, but are agnostic over whether all properties are essentially dispositional; certainly, they do not explicitly endorse dispositional monism.Footnote 10 For MD, it is sufficient for an object to have dispositions if it instantiates certain dispositional properties.Footnote 11 But, Borghini and Williams make a distinction between dispositions and the dispositional properties that those dispositions are grounded by. They cite two reasons (and both are owed to Molnar (2003)): Firstly, (for some properties) from one dispositional property, many different manifestations can arise; and secondly, when combined with different combinations of dispositional properties, the same dispositional property can give rise to different manifestations.Footnote 12 Moreover, Borghini and Williams (2008) maintain: dispositional properties are not extrinsic, but are intrinsic, and this is why dispositions need never manifest.

Now, as mentioned, dispositions are modal; and so, MD is not fully modally reductive. Borghini and Williams (2008: 33) maintain, however: “dispositions are something we need in our ontology anyway” whatever modal theory one endorses; so, they ask: why would one wish to reduce possibility to something else “if the dispositions can deal with [possibility] themselves?”. MD, then, is the view that metaphysical modality is reducible to one modal notion: dispositionality.

And so, to analyse atomic possibility in terms of dispositionality,Footnote 13 MD provides the following biconditional:

  • (AP) For any atomic state of affairs, S, S is possible ↔ some actual objects have some dispositional properties d1,…, dn, which ground some disposition D, which has as its manifestation, S.Footnote 14

One can observe that AP coheres with dispositional realism’s contention that dispositions need not ever actually manifest. Likewise, it need only be the case that some actual object bears D, for S to be possible. Further, S will, in addition to being possible, be actual, if D manifests at some actual time, t; so, any actual state of affairs will also be possible given that the actual manifestations of dispositions ground actual states of affairs; and so, the (T)-axiom, ‘◻A→ A’, is affirmed by MD.

Additionally, MD admits that if anything is a constituent of D’s manifestation, that constituent is rendered possible by D’s existence. Thus, for any relevant, say, “general” possibility, D’s existence will ground the truth of that general possibility if it is a constituent of D’s manifestation (Borghini and Williams 2008: 27). Thus, in addition to grounding the possibility of shattering, a teacup’s being fragile grounds the following possibility: <possibly: at least one teacup exists>.Footnote 15

And so, MD is an actualist and naturalist theory that semantically reduces and ontologically explicates possibility in terms of dispositionality: MD is actualist, because the dispositions of actual objects are the truth-makers of all possibility claims; and MD is naturalist, because objects’ dispositions are spatiotemporal and causal.

3 MD’s Formal Deficiency: The Invalidation of (T)

Now, there are (at least) two types of objection to MD.Footnote 16 The first objection-type concerns MD’s material deficiency, and asks: does MD ascribe the correct truth values to certain intuitively true modal claims? Those who answer negatively point to certain intuitively true unactualised possibilities, and demonstrate MD’s inability to ascribe the correct truth values to claims pertaining to those possibilities by highlighting the fact that, on MD, such claims lack appropriate truth-makers.Footnote 17 The second objection-type concerns MD’s formal deficiency, and asks: does MD validate all desirable modal logical axioms? Those who answer negatively point to certain intuitively true actualised possibilities (or necessities), and demonstrate MD’s inability to validate certain modal logical axioms, through the lack of truth-makers for claims pertaining to those possibilities.

Here I argue for MD’s formal deficiency. I argue: neither Yates’s (2015) nor Allen’s (2017) respective responses to Yates’s (2015) objection that (T) is invalid on MD is successful.Footnote 18

Recall: for MD, since actual manifestations of dispositions ground actual states of affairs, any actual state of affairs will also be possible. Accordingly, this affirms (T): ‘A → ◊A’ (or, contrapositively: ‘□A → A’). The truth of (T) seems indisputable: were (T) not included in our modal logic, ‘□A’ would not express the claim ‘necessarily: A’, since the notion of it being necessary that A is the notion that it could not possibly be the case that not-A, and so A cannot be anything but true if □A is true. Thus, it goes without saying that any modal theory should validate (T).Footnote 19 However, as noted by Yates (2015), MD invalidates (T). To provide the objection, I use Yates’s (2015: 413) biconditionals for the claims of the forms ‘◊A’ and ‘□A’, which use second-order quantification over dispositions:

  • (Where ‘∃D〉[p](D)’ = ‘there exists a disposition D such that D has p as its manifestation’)

  • (POSS) ◊p ↔ ∃D〉[p](D)

  • (NEC) □p ↔ ¬∃D〉[¬p](D).Footnote 20

Now, consider the claim: ‘1 + 2 = 3’. By NEC, if ‘¬∃D〉[‘¬(1 + 2 = 3)’](D)’ is true, then ‘1 + 2 = 3’ is necessarily true. Since this condition seems satisfied, we therefore get: ‘□(1 + 2 = 3)’. This is the correct result: true mathematical propositions should be necessarily true. Moreover, since whatever is necessary is also possible, we also get: ‘◊(1 + 2 = 3)’. Now, by POSS, if ‘∃D〉[‘1 + 2 = 3′](D)’ is true, ‘1 + 2 = 3′ is possible. This condition, however, seems unsatisfied: specifically, there fails to exist an object with a disposition which has ‘1 + 2 = 3′ as its manifestation. Certainly, there exist dispositions that, if manifested, ‘1 + 2 = 3′ would be true – but this is distinct to there existing a particular disposition that grounds the truth of ‘1 + 2 = 3′. So, by POSS, we therefore get: ‘¬◊(1 + 2 = 3)’ (which, given ‘¬◊A ↔ □¬A’, we also get: ‘□¬(1 + 2 = 3)’).

So, on MD, when considering ‘1 + 2 = 3’, we get two sets of claims: {‘□(1 + 2 = 3)’, ‘¬◊(1 + 2 = 3)’} and {‘□¬(1 + 2 = 3)’, ‘◊(1 + 2 = 3)’}. Clearly then, (T) fails: ‘□(1+2=3) → 1+2=3’ is invalid, since ‘□¬(1 + 2 = 3)’ is true, and ‘□¬(1 + 2 = 3)’ entails that necessarily ‘1 + 2 = 3’ is false; and ‘1+2=3 → ◊(1+2=3)’ is invalid, since ‘¬◊(1 + 2 = 3)’ is true.

The problem, I believe, stems from the fact that the truth-makers for ‘1 + 2 = 3’ seem to be categorical properties. So, if this is the case, it is perhaps not surprising that claims like ‘1 + 2 = 3’ deliver odd results on MD’s biconditionals – after all, MD’s biconditionals analyse modal claims by appealing to dispositions, which, on MD, are exclusively ontologically supported by dispositional properties, not categorical properties. Thus, since, for MD, all modal claims are made-true by dispositions, which are grounded by dispositional properties, any claim that has categorical properties as a truth-maker can be used to demonstrate that MD invalidates (T).

Now, there are two plausible responses in the literature: one is owed to Yates (2015) and the other to Allen (2017). I argue that both responses fail.

The first response proposes installing truth into MD’s biconditionals, so by stipulation (T) holds – here are the biconditionals (Yates 2015: 419):

  • (POSS*) ◊p ↔ {p ∨ ∃D〉[p](D)}.

  • (NEC*) □p ↔ {p ∧ ¬∃D〉[¬p](D)}.

So, since ‘1 + 2 = 3’ is true, ‘1 + 2 = 3’ is possible. Thence, (T) holds.

Now, Yates (2015: 412) claims that “[he] see[s] no reason why” MDists should not “embrace [his] amendments” to the biconditionals. I do see why, however: installing truth into the biconditionals is tantamount to rejecting MD’s core claim: i.e., that all modal facts are made-true by dispositions alone. Thus, MDists welcome this solution on pain of rejecting MD’s principal tenet and thereby limiting dispositions’ capacity to ground modality. Now, Yates does accept that his solution renders MD-like theories weak rather than strong. But, I am not as sanguine about adopting the solution as he is – MDists, I argue, should not adopt the solution: installing truth into the biconditionals is not mere tinkering – Yates’s solution requires a fundamental change to the nature of MD.Footnote 21 Indeed, Yates’s response here should seem odd to MDists: MDists wish to know why it is that claims such as ‘1 + 2 = 3′ are true and necessarily true, and MD should informatively explain this – indeed, MDists do not merely wish to know whether such claims simply are true, they wish to know why they are true. Certainly, on possible worlds accounts, truth is installed into the biconditionals: ‘possibly: p ↔ at some world: p’ and ‘necessarily: p ↔ at all worlds: p’. However, I take it that part of MDists’ aversion to possible worlds accounts of modality is precisely that truth is installed into the biconditionals (very often) with no further informative explanation for why, say, a certain proposition just so happens to be true at some world. It seems that a virtue of MD is that, through its actualism, naturalism, and dispositionalism, MDists can provide true modal claims with informative explanations for why they are true: there is some causal and spatiotemporal explanation for why <possibly: p > is true – that possibility claim is true, not simply by virtue of its being true at the world, but by virtue of causal and spatiotemporal features of the world, namely, dispositions. Indeed, it seems (at least part of) the reason for propounding MD is to provide an informative explanation of why certain claims are necessarily true, but if we can now simply say that (at least some) necessity claims are true if their corresponding non-modal claims are true with no positive dispositionalist grounding to account for their being true, dispositions seem redundant. And, if dispositions are now not required to do the work that MDists thought they did, why should MDists not provide a simpler account, and analyse all modal claims purely in terms of truth? That is, why should MDists not provide the following biconditionals?

  • (POSS**) ◊p ↔ {p}.

  • (NEC**) □p ↔ {p ∧ ¬(¬p)}.

The answer from MDists, I take it, would be: Part of our motivation for positing MD, and part of our reason for rejecting possible worlds, is that we wish to provide a causal and spatiotemporal (that is: a naturalist) explanation of why it is that certain true claims are necessarily true: analysing modality in terms of dispositions allows us to provide such an explanation. Necessary truths should not float free from, or be prior to, or be more basic than, dispositions; dispositions should be more basic than, or be prior to, or not float free from, necessary truths. Thus, if MDists were happy to accept Yates’s conclusion that MD cannot account for, say, mathematical necessities in terms of dispositions, then rather than accept Yates’s amendment of installing truth into the biconditionals to account for mathematical truths, it seems MDists should instead concern themselves exclusively with providing truthmakers for, say, nomic possibilities and necessities.Footnote 22

Now, one might contend that Yates’s modal distinction which entails that necessary mathematical truths are not grounded by dispositions is justifiable; indeed, Yates only revises the biconditional to deal with such necessary truths.Footnote 23 I am unconvinced here: certainly, it is sometimes claimed that necessary facts are brute; but, as I note above, I take it that the MDist would reject this claim on explanatory grounds. But, even if such a distinction can be justified, such that MDists can accept that some necessities are brute, and so can accept that their naturalist explanatory project does not extend to such necessities, it is unclear that such a distinction would render the theory preferable to the possible worlds framework, all things considered: sure, MD might be able to provide a more satisfactory explanation of why, say, it is possible that I be a concert pianist, but a possible worlds theory can provide theoretical unity. It is at best unclear which virtue is preferable.

Perhaps, however, it could be contended that the truth claims within the respective right-halves of the biconditionals POSS* and NEC* (and POSS** and NEC**) are true by virtue of the actual manifestations of dispositions.Footnote 24 Certainly, one may attempt to provide a dispositionalist account of, say, mathematical truths – and I consider this strategy below – however, it is then unclear why truth is installed into the biconditionals’ respective right-halves; if, for instance, the claim ‘p’ within ‘{p ∨ ∃D〉[p](D)}’ is true by virtue of an actual manifestation of a disposition, then why should the ‘p’ be included in the biconditional at all? The ‘p’ would be redundant.Footnote 25

For these reasons, then, I believe Yates’s response is not available to the MDist.

So, let us examine the second response, suggested by Allen (2017). Her response, in essence, is as follows: MDists should ontologically construe all properties as essentially dispositional properties; that is, to espouse, what I referred to earlier as, dispositional monism. Now, Wang (2015: 456) claims: “defender[s] of essentially dispositional properties need not ban categorical properties”. But, to avoid invalidating (T), MDists may have to.Footnote 26 So, paradigmatic categorical properties are now taken to be dispositional properties which support dispositions that, following Hütteman’s (2013) terminology, continuously manifest. Thus, the truth-maker for ‘1 + 2 = 3’ is a continuously manifesting disposition, which is grounded by certain dispositional properties. But, one must ask: which objects have these dispositional properties? The first option is to say: all objects. This seems absurd, however: indeed, (without calling upon merely ad hoc reasons) why do I, my cat and my laptop each have dispositional properties that support a continuously-manifesting disposition for ‘1 + 2 = 3’? Thus, we must move to the second option, which is to say: some objects.Footnote 27 At this point Allen provides two ontological options, which both – she believes – help MD validate (T). Now, strictly speaking, Allen is correct here, both options do validate (T) – I do not deny that, like I did not deny that Yates’s response validated (T). But, I do argue, in the way that I argued against Yates’s response, that Allen’s prescribed solutions validate (T) only at a high cost to MD. Let us examine Allen’s ontological options.

The first option Allen sketches is to claim that numbers, as abstracta, instantiate certain dispositional properties that ground certain dispositions. So, the dispositional properties of the abstract mathematical objects, 1, 2 and 3, when combined, produce the continuously-manifesting-disposition that make-true the claim: ‘1 + 2 = 3’. Now, Allen briefly mentions that, whilst a Platonist about dispositions might welcome this suggestion, an Aristotelian might not – and arguably, MDists are Aristotelians.Footnote 28 But, there is, however, a sufficiently strong objection to Allen’s first suggestion, which, I believe, demonstrates why MDists should not adopt such an ontological construal of mathematical objects (or at any rate should be rather cautious about adopting such an ontological picture). Specifically, this option, I argue, jars with MD’s naturalism.Footnote 29 Naturalism is the view that objects’ dispositions are spatiotemporal and causal. Now, since abstracta are not spatiotemporal, it is reasonable to suppose that neither are their dispositions, if they have any. Moreover, it is conventional to regard abstracta as causally inert, that is, abstract entitles are non-causal; and, since the entities are non-causal, it is reasonable to suppose that neither are their dispositions, (again) if they have any.Footnote 30 So, I argue: MDists are permitted to use the dispositions of numbers, which are taken as abstract entities, to ground mathematical necessities, only if they are willing to violate MD’s naturalism – a core feature of MD. Of course, MDists are at liberty, for a price, to violate their naturalism – indeed, often the point of raising objections to theories and proposals is to better understand the costs involved in adopting those theories and proposals. However, it seems, to me at least, that since naturalism is such a core feature of MD’s account of modality, permitting certain violations of naturalism, at best, presents a high price for MDists to pay, and, at worst, distorts MD to the extent that it no longer sufficiently resembles Borghini and Williams’s original theory.

So, we have Allen’s second ontological option: adopt physicalism about numbers – that is, numbers existentially depend upon actual, concrete objects. So, the constantly-manifesting dispositions of (at least some) concrete objects make-true mathematical necessities. This view – although congruous with MD’s naturalism – is certainly, I believe, unusual and antiquated (and plausibly antiquated for a good reason (although, I do not think that something’s merely being antiquated is reason in itself to reject that something!)).Footnote 31 It additionally seems that we have returned to the question: which objects have the relevant dispositions to ground mathematical necessities? Indeed, we originally thought it absurd that all objects have dispositions that ground mathematical necessities, so if MDists agree with that being absurd, they must now claim that only some concrete objects have dispositions that ground mathematical necessities. But this latter claim, I believe, seems more absurd than the former: why is it that members of one concrete object-type, and not members of another, have dispositions that ground mathematical necessities? Surely it would seem extremely odd that certain concrete objects have certain dispositions that ground mathematical necessities and certain other concrete objects do not.Footnote 32 So, I argue: if MDists adopt physicalism about numbers, their theory is at best extremely bizarre and at worst absurd. Now, accepting either consequence is perhaps a price worth paying; but, since I am not an MDist, the price is not mine to pay, and, at any rate, MDists will have a better understanding of how large their purses are.Footnote 33

And so: contra Allen, both ontological options, I believe, fail, or at least present substantial costs; thus, this second response, I believe, is also unavailable to MDists – or at least is available only at a high price.

Therefore, since both the most plausible responses to MD’s invalidation of (T) are unsuccessful (or at least present rather high costs), MD should be rejected (or the cost better be demonstrated to be worth it). Unlike perhaps some logical axioms, rejecting (T) is non-negotiable.Footnote 34