Skip to main content
Log in

Davidson and a Twist of Wittgenstein: Metaontology, Self-Canceling Paradox, and Settled Insight

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper proposes with Davidson that the talk of metaontology is literally meaningless, but with Wittgenstein that it is so in a way that grants a unique type of insight. More specifically, it argues both that Davidson’s arguments have a cogency that is hard to dismiss, and also that, since his own arguments are metaontological, they are self-referential, and consequently in turn undermine their own meaning as well. The paper argues further that metaontological statements cannot be avoided. Consequently, this kind of statement constitutes an unavoidable self-referential paradox that means what it also excludes as capable of meaning. The result is a reinstatement of the meaning of ontological insight and in fact, the paper argues, a deep enrichment and also a particularly cogent justification of it. In addition, the logical peculiarity of the paradox involved has further useful consequences for the outcome of this justification, including a mutually illuminating commonality with some versions of metaethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, the collection of essays in Chalmers et al. (2009).

  2. It looks as though this reinstatement cannot happen, as once meaning is lost there is simply nothing meaningful to work with any longer. It also looks as though my statement should be more precisely worded, so as not to say that the meaning of these arguments is lost, but that they turn out never to have had meaning at all. I think these objections are only partly right, however, and I shall defend this view in discussing the “resolute reading” of Wittgenstein toward the end of section 2 below.

  3. The position Winch is responding to is one argued by Alasdair MacIntyre early in his career. He argues for the idea that, in evaluating the rationality of “primitive societies,” we cannot help but take recourse to and so come “to recognize the appropriateness of scientific criteria of judgment from our standpoint” (1970, 67; previously published in Hick 1964). We are brought to recognize that there are no other conceivable criteria for rationality, and so “our” criteria are not meaningfully described as “ours,” either: they are not culturally specific and so imposed by us; they are simply the criteria for rationality, not “ours,” not specifiable as “these” criteria rather than “those.” (A little below in the text I quote MacIntyre’s later criticism of the Davidsonian position his early argument endorsed!) Winch’s response, given more fully than in the text above, is that “his argument . . . does not in fact show that our own standards of rationality occupy a peculiarly central position. The appearance to the contrary is an optical illusion engendered by the fact that MacIntyre’s case has been advanced in the English language and in the context of twentieth Century European culture. But a formally similar argument could be advanced in any language containing concepts playing a similar role in that language to those of ‘intelligibility’ and ‘rationality’ in ours” (1964, 318).

  4. Putnam is in fact discussing Richard Rorty’s view here, but it is a view that, as Putnam discusses (1994, 300), Rorty argues is the same as Davidson’s; and although Putnam reads Davidson differently in important respects from the way Rorty does, the problem he identifies clearly applies to the aspects of Davidson’s view that I have been discussing. The logic of the relevant issue is the same.

  5. Dupuy (2000) offers a technical defense of the intelligibility and legitimacy of this kind of retroactive shift of truth over time, in the context of “backward induction” in rational choice theory.

  6. I discuss the sense and legitimacy of this paradox in more detail in Barris (2012) and at length in Barris (2015).

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. 2005.  Human life, action, and ethics (Eds: Geach M. and Gormally L.). Charlottesville: Imprint Academic.

  • Barris, J. (2012). The convergent conceptions of being in mainstream analytic and postmodern continental philosophy. Metaphilosophy, 43(5), 592-618.

  • Barris, J. (2015). Sometimes always true: Undogmatic pluralism in politics, metaphysics, and epistemology. New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Bremer, M. (2005). An introduction to paraconsistent logics. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2009). Ontological anti-realism.  In Chalmers et al. (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 77–129). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Chalmers, D., Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (Eds.). (2009). Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. 1993. Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein, and nonsense. In Cohen T, Guyer P, and Putnam H (Eds.), Pursuits of Reason: Essays in Honor of Stanley Cavell (pp. 195–224). Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press.

  • Crary, A., & Read, R. (Eds.). (2000). The new Wittgenstein. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984a). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In Davidson, D., Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 183–98). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidson, D. (1984b). Reality without reference. In Davidson, D., Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 215–225). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In Lepore, E. (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 433–46). Cambridge: Blackwell.

  • Diamond, C. (1991). Throwing away the ladder: How to read the Tractatus. In Diamond, C., The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy, and the mind (pp. 179–204). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Dupuy, J.-P. (2000). Philosophical foundations of a new concept of equilibrium in the social sciences: Projected equilibrium. Philosophical Studies, 100, 323–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, M. 2009. Carnap and ontological pluralism. In Chalmers et al. (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 130–156). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Gaita, R. (2004). Good and evil: An absolute conception (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (Ed.). (1964). Faith and the philosophers. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, R. F. (1980). Against empiricism: On education, epistemology and value. Totowa: Barnes & Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnstone Jr., H. W. (1978). Validity and rhetoric in philosophical argument: An outlook in transition. University Park: The Dialogue Press of Man and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1973). Principles of nature and of grace, founded on reason. In G. H. R. Parkinson (Ed.), M. Morris & G. H. R. Parkinson (trans.). Leibniz: Philosophical writings (pp. 195–204). London. Dent & Sons.

  • Livingston, P. M. (2012). The politics of logic: Badiou, Wittgenstein, and the consequences of formalism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. C. (1970). Is understanding religion compatible with believing? In Wilson, B. R. (Ed.), Rationality (pp. 62–77). London: Basil Blackwell.

  • MacIntyre, A. C. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal Questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1961). Republic (trans: Shorey, P.). In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), Plato: The collected dialogues. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Price, H. 2009. Metaphysics after Carnap: The ghost who walks? In Chalmers et al (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 320–346). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Priest, G. (2001). An introduction to non-classical logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2002). Beyond the limits of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1990. Truth and convention. In Putnam, H., Realism with a human face (Ed: Conant, J.) (96-104). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Putnam, H. 1994. The question of realism. In Putnam, H., Words and life (Ed: Conant, J.) (295-314). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Rhees, R. 1999. Moral questions (Ed: D. Z. Phillips). London: Macmillan.

  • Rorty, R. (1998). Truth and progress: Philosophical papers volume 3. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R. M. (1995). Paradoxes (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. 2009. Being, existence, and ontological commitment. In Chalmers et al. (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 472–506). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Williams, M. (1996). Unnatural doubts: Epistemological realism and the basis of Scepticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1964). Understanding a primitive society. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1(4), 307–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1972). Ethics and action. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (trans: Anscombe, G. E. M.). Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (trans: Pears, D. F. & McGuinness, B. F.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1967. Zettel (Eds: Anscombe, G. E. M. & Von Wright, G. H., trans: Anscombe, G. E. M.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeremy Barris.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barris, J. Davidson and a Twist of Wittgenstein: Metaontology, Self-Canceling Paradox, and Settled Insight. Philosophia 46, 255–274 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9928-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9928-7

Keywords

Navigation