Skip to main content
Log in

How Emotions do not Provide Reasons to Act

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

If emotions provide reasons for action through their intentional content, as is often argued, where does this leave the role of the affective element of an emotion? Can it be more than a motivator and have significant bearing of its own on our emotional actions, as actions done for reasons? One way it can is through reinforcing other reasons that we might have, as Greenspan (2011) argues. Central to Greenspan’s account is the claim that the affective discomfort of an emotion, as a fact about the agent’s state of being, provides an additional normative reason to act to alleviate the state. This, I argue, is not correct, nor is it the best way to understand emotions as reason-reinforcers. In this paper, I thus do two things: I provide an examination of how and why the affect of emotion could provide reasons to act to alleviate it and I propose that the real way emotions reinforce reasons is through the way they orient our attention onto things that matter, registering them as salient.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Chapter 1 in Deonna and Teroni (2012) for a discussion of the differences between these and other affective phenomena, such as sentiments.

  2. Although see Deonna and Teroni (2012) for a recent challenge to the claim that it is the content of an emotion that is evaluative. Rather, they argue that emotions are evaluative attitudes taken towards non-evaluative content. This challenge, as far as I can see, makes no difference to the issues under discussion in this paper and so I set it aside to focus on the more widespread understanding of emotions as having an evaluative intentional content.

  3. Greenspan focuses on moral reasons and the moral realm in (2011), but the same story would hold for non-moral reasons, as she discusses in her earlier (1988) book.

  4. Greenspan makes use of her ‘critical conception’ of reasons (Greenspan 2005, 2007, 2010, 2011). On this critical conception, giving reasons for action either answers or offers criticism. Favouring reasons answer criticism of an action, whereas critical reasons offer criticism of an action. Favouring reasons are optional and can justify an action, but they do not impose normative requirements on the agent. Critical reasons, in contrast, do impose normative requirements. This critical conception of reasons is not dominant in the literature, where normative reasons are usually said to count in favour of some action and the normative relation is one of favouring rather than one of criticising. However, there are similar approaches to be found, such as those of Raz (1999), Dancy (2004) and Gert (2004). In any event, Greenspan argues that emotions provide additional critical reasons (which she also calls normative reasons in places). While I choose to frame my discussion in terms of normative reasons, my arguments against Greenspan’s claim that discomfort provides a reason – focusing on what makes a state of discomfort unpleasant or bad – serve to show that emotions do not provide critical reasons. This is because being a critical reason requires that the agent is criticisable if she fails to act on it. In order to be criticisable, there must be something about the discomfort as a fact about the agent’s state of being that is bad. If there is nothing inherently bad, as I shall argue, then we are not criticisable for remaining in a state of discomfort.

  5. Thanks to Julien Deonna for the example.

  6. Harmon-Jones et al. (2013), in fact, define affective states along these three dimensions.

  7. A challenge for offering a successful account of pain is to show how the unpleasantness of pain can motivate and rationalise pain avoidance actions by providing motivating reasons for those actions. While the focus for pain is on motivating reasons and mine is on normative reasons, the challenge for pain theorists is similar to the challenge I am tackling here, of showing how an experience of a certain kind is unpleasant (and hence bad for the agent). It is thus useful to draw on this literature for current purposes and I do so, with care, throughout.

  8. See also Scanlon (1998), amongst others, for the claim that desires do not provide reasons. Focusing specifically on desires and pain, see Bain (2013) and Helm (2009). Admittedly, whether desires can provide normative reasons is a debated point but defending it is beyond the scope of this paper.

  9. And this is not what Greenspan claims, as shall be discussed below.

  10. According to evaluativists about pain, the motivational state of unpleasant pain is one that represents bodily damage as bad, and the experience of that representation of badness is itself bad or unpleasant (Bain 2014). So, it is the experience of something being evaluated positively or negatively that is important.

  11. ‘Self-evaluation’ is my term, not Greenspan’s.

References

  • Alvarez, M. (2010). Kinds of Reasons: An Essay in the Philosophy of Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Oxford Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1962). Bodily Sensations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2002). On acting rationally against one’s best judgment. In Unprincipled Virtue: An Inquiry Into Moral Agency (pp. 33–65). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. (2013). Pain. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/pain/.

  • Bain, D. (2013). What makes pains unpleasant? Philosophical Studies, 166, S69–S89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, D. (2014). Pains that don’t hurt. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 305–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Ze’ev, A. (2000). The Subtlety of Emotion. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. (2013). Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castelfranchi, C., & Miceli, M. (2009). The cognitive-motivational compound of emotional experience. Emotion Review, 1, 223–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charland, L. C. (2005). The heat of emotion valence and the demarcation problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12, 82–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clore, G. (1994). Why emotions are felt. In P. Ekman & R. Davidson (Eds.), The Nature of Emotion (pp. 103–111). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Fulkerson, M. (2014). Affect, rationalization, and motivation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5, 103–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2005). Appraising valence. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12, 103–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Enticing reasons. In R. J. Wallace, S. Scheffler, & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and Value: Themes From the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 91–118). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, R. (1987). The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2012). The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Döring, S. (2007). Seeing what to do: Affective perception and rational motivation. Dialectica, 61, 363–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2008). Emotion and understanding. In G. Brun, U. Doguoglu, & D. Kuenzle (Eds.), Epistemology and Emotions (pp. 33–50). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faucher, L., & Tappolet, C. (2002). Fear and the focus of attention. Consciousness and Emotion, 3, 105–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gert, J. (2004). Brute Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2000). The Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (1988). Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (2005). Asymmetrical practical reasons. In M. E. Reicher & J. C. Marek (Eds.), Experience and Analysis: Papers of the 27th Wittgenstein Symposium (pp. 387–394). Vienna: HPT&öBV.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (2007). Practical reasons and moral ‘ought’. In R. Schafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 2, pp. 172–194). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (2010). Making room for options: Moral reasons, imperfect duties, and choice. Social Philosophy and Policy, 27, 181–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (2011). Craving the right: Emotions and moral reasons. In C. Bagnoli (Ed.), Morality and the Emotions (pp. 39–60). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, R. (2008). If it itches, scratch! Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86(4), 525-535.

  • Harmon-Jones, E., Gable, P. A., & Price, T. F. (2013). Does negative affect always narrow and positive affect always broaden the mind? Considering the influence of motivational intensity on cognitive scope. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22, 301–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (2009). Emotions as evaluative feelings. Emotion Review, 1, 248–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9, 188–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2001). The authority of affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 181-214.

  • Jones, K. (2003). Emotions, weakness of will, and the normative conception of agency. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions (pp. 181–200). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2007). An imperative theory of pain. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 517–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambie, J. A. (2009). Emotion experience, rational action, and self-knowledge. Emotion Review, 1, 272–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moller, D. (2011). Anticipated emotions and emotional valence. Philosophers’ Imprint, 11, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oatley, K., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1987). Towards a cognitive theory of emotions. Cognition & Emotion, 1, 29–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut Reactions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, W. (1993). Putting rationality in its place. In Morality and Action (pp. 228–255). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1999). Practical Reasons and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, A., & Buhle, J. (2006). Typologies of attentional networks. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7(5), 367–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisenzein, R., & Döring, S. A. (2009). Ten perspectives on emotional experience: Introduction to the special issue. Emotion Review, 1, 195–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2010). Emotion, motivation, and action: The case of fear. In P. Goldie (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion (pp. 325–345). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank a number of people for their insightful feedback on earlier versions of this paper. In particular, I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for this journal, Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi, Julien Deonna, Fabrice Teroni, Tristram Oliver-Skuse, and the members of Thumos, the Genevan Research Group on Emotions, Values and Norms. This work was supported by the National Centre for Competence in Research (NCCR) ‘Affective Sciences’.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mary Carman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Carman, M. How Emotions do not Provide Reasons to Act. Philosophia 46, 555–574 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9896-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9896-y

Keywords

Navigation