Skip to main content
Log in

Contest and Indifference: Two Models of Open-Minded Inquiry

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While open-mindedness as an intellectual trait has been recognized for centuries, Western philosophers have not explicitly endorsed it as a virtue until recently. This acknowledgment has been roughly coincident with the rise of virtue epistemology. As with any virtue, it is important to inform contemporary discussion of open-mindedness with reflection on sources from the history of philosophy. Here I do just this. After reviewing two major accounts of open-mindedness, which I dub "Contest" and "Indifference," I explore some ideas pertinent to the subject in four philosophers spanning eighteen centuries: Sextus Empiricus, John Locke, John Stuart Mill, and Paul Feyerabend. Despite their varying concerns and terminology, their contributions may valuably inform current reflection on the virtue of open-mindedness, whether construed in terms of the Contest or Indifference account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Hare acknowledges, he is indebted to Bertrand Russell who first used the phrase “critical receptiveness” as a way of characterizing open-mindedness. See Russell (1950).

  2. It should be noted, though, that Locke, following his medieval forbears, did believe there to be a supreme academic discipline, namely theology. He expounds upon this point in Of the Conduct of the Understanding, section 23.

  3. This phrase “anything goes” has been subject to a variety of interpretations. For a critical examination of some of the major epistemological and socio-political interpretations of this thesis, see Russell (1983).

  4. Feyerabend actually speaks to this issue specifically when he uses it to illustrate his advocacy for a “pluralistic methodology” in science. In using such a method and hearing all views, a scientist “may then discover that the theory of evolution is not as good as is generally assumed and that it must be supplemented, or entirely replaced, by an improved version of Genesis” (p. 14).

  5. There are plenty of other significant scientific advancements that arose by irrational means. Examples include Rontgen’s accidental discovery of x-ray technology, Kekule’s solving the puzzle of the chemical configuration of benzene in a dream, Fleming’s accidental discovery of penicillin antibiotics, and Spencer’s invention of the microwave oven.

  6. This publication benefited from a research fellowship at Biola University's Center for Christian Thought, which was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.

References

  • Baehr, J. (2011). The inquiring mind: On intellectual virtues and virtue epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (2002). John Stuart Mill and the ends of life. In Liberty: Incorporating four essays on liberty. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Empiricus, S. (1976). Outlines of Pyrrhonism. R. G. Bury (trans.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1978). Science in a free society. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (2010). Against method (4th ed.). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, P. (1993). Should we teach children to be open-minded? Or, is the Pope open-minded about the existence of God? Journal of Philosophy of Education, 27(1), 39–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, W. (1987). Open-mindedness in moral education: three contemporary approaches. Journal of Moral Education, 16(2), 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, W. (2003). The ideal of open-mindedness and its place in education. Journal of Thought, 38(2), 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, W. (2005). What is open-mindedness? In W. Hare & J. P. Portelli (Eds.), Key questions for educators (pp. 16–19). Halifax: Edphil Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, W. (2009). What open-mindedness requires. Skeptical Inquirer, 33(2), 36–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1996). Some thoughts concerning understanding and of the conduct of the understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • McEvoy, J. G. (1975). A ‘revolutionary’ philosophy of science: Feyerabend and the degeneration of critical rationalism into sceptical fallibilism. Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 49–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1956). On liberty. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Russell, B. (1950). Can we afford to keep open minds? New York Times Magazine, 9, 37–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (1983). Anything goes. Social Studies of Science, 13(3), 437–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stough, C. (1984). Sextus Empiricus on non-assertion. Phronesis, 29(2), 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Striker, G. (1990). Ataraxia: happiness as tranquility. The Monist, 73(1), 97–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tibbets, P. (1977). Feyerabend’s “against method”: the case for methodological pluralism. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 7(3), 265–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff, N. (1996). John Locke and the ethics of belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James S. Spiegel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Spiegel, J.S. Contest and Indifference: Two Models of Open-Minded Inquiry. Philosophia 45, 789–810 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9850-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9850-z

Keywords

Navigation