Skip to main content
Log in

Music Pluralism, Music Realism, and Music Archaeology

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to pluralism about some concept, there are multiple non-equivalent, legitimate concepts pertaining to the (alleged) ontological category in question. It is an open question whether conceptual pluralism implies anti-realism about that category. In this article, I argue that at least for the case of music, it does not. To undermine the application of an influential move from pluralism (about music concepts) to anti-realism (about the music category), then, I provide an argument in support of indifference realism about music, by appeal to music archaeological research, via an analogy with Adrian Currie’s indifference realism about species licensed by paleobiological research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

(Figure from Longrich and Field (2012); reproduced here under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Licence. Source = https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0032623.g001. Accessed 2 May 2019.)

Fig. 2

(Figure from Adler (2009); reproduced here with permission of Springer Nature. Image: H. Jensen/Univ. Tübingen.)

Fig. 3

(Figure freely distributable and adaptable under Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 2.5 Generic licence. Source = https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/3/3f/Flauta_paleol%C3%ADtica.jpg. Accessed 2 May 2019. Image: José-Manuel Benito Álvarez.)

Fig. 4

(Figure is reproducible under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 2.0 Generic License; Source = https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/7c/Fl%C3%BBte_pal%C3%A9olithique_%28mus%C3%A9e_national_de_Slov%C3%A9nie%2C_Ljubljana%29_%289420310527%29.jpg. Accessed 17 April 2018. Image: Jean-Pierre Dalbéra.)

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Maconie (1990) for the idea that what counts as music is subjectively determined by each individual.

  2. In this article, ‘monism’ and ‘pluralism’ are theses about concepts; ‘realism’ and ‘anti-realism’ are theses about ontological categories. I use ‘anti-realism (about x)’ and ‘ontological eliminativism (about x)’ interchangeably. (This is a stylistic matter; other philosophers might distinguish anti-realism from ontological eliminativism, say, as a claim about dependence rather than existence.) One could also subscribe to linguistic eliminativism, and argue that the term ‘music’ should be eliminated from discourse. This is a logically independent position from ontological eliminativism and I do not address it in this article.

  3. For an erudite discussion of the rise of conceptual pluralism in philosophy of science, see Taylor and Vickers (2017).

  4. They might not be, if, for example, classical Mendelian genetics has been ‘superseded’ by molecular genetics, or if molecular genetics turns out to be wrongheaded.

  5. For example, Barker (2018) illustrates how four moth populations and two liverwort populations are grouped differently according to different species concepts.

  6. There are, of course, other approaches to defending anti-realism about species (see, e.g., Mishler 1999) and to eliminativism about a pluralistic concept more generally (e.g., Taylor and Vickers 2017). Needless to say, a full exposition of the species debate is beyond the scope of this article, as is a survey of strategies for defending eliminativism-given-pluralism. The present article is concerned with the kind of move made by Ereshefsky; other approaches require other treatments best left for another time. I thank an anonymous referee for pushing me on this.

  7. Thus ‘indifference realism’, as it used in this article, is independent of the indifference realism of Medieval philosopher William of Champeaux, a theory of universals according to which distinct individuals may be ‘the same’ in certain respects despite there being no ‘shared essences’ (see Guilfoy 2012).

  8. This is so even if paleobiologists operate with a specific notion of species, idiosyncratic or otherwise. As an anonymous referee points out, many paleobiologists operate with a notion of species as independently evolving lineages.

  9. Here I add that vindicatory indifference excludes debunking cases. Assuming for the moment that there is a plurality of concepts of such (alleged) categories as, e.g., gods, ghosts and spirits, legitimate scientific research into these categories that is conceptually indifferent does not licence realism about them. I thank [name redacted] for pushing me on this point.

  10. To determine ‘what is true in a venially impossible fiction such as the Holmes stories’, Lewis (1978) suggests shifting one’s analysis ‘from the original impossible fiction to the several possible revised versions that stay closest to the original’ (1978, p. 46). Lewis’s idea, then, is that what is true in the Holmes stories is what is true in all of these closest possible fictions (and he provides two analyses for determining truth in those fictions). Needless to say, whether Lewis’s framework for determining truth in fiction is a good one or not is not our concern here.

  11. For discussion, see e.g., Both (2009), Morley (2013), and Killin (2018).

  12. Mithen even goes so far as to claim that ‘all modern humans are relatively limited in their musical abilities when compared with the Neanderthals. This is partly because the Neanderthals evolved neural networks for the musical features of ‘Hmmmmm’ that did not evolve in the Homo sapiens lineage, and partly because the evolution of language has inhibited the musical abilities inherited from the common ancestor we share with Homo neanderthalensis’ (2005, p. 245). Unsurprisingly, such comments have been criticised for being wildly speculative.

  13. See e.g., Mithen (2005), Tuniz et al. (2012), Morley (2013), and Killin (2016, 2017, 2018).

  14. See http://www.nms.si/en. Accessed 2 May 2019. In particular, see http://www.nms.si/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=2089%3Aneandertaleva-pial-pial-iz-divjih-bab&catid=18%3Aznameniti-predmeti&Itemid=33&lang=en.

  15. This example has received attention from various philosophers of music, e.g., Dodd (2018), Kania (2010), Davies (2004), and Levinson (1990).

  16. This discussion expands upon the point Currie (2016) mentions in passing.

References

  • Adler D (2009) The earliest musical tradition. Nature 460:695–696

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker MJ (2018) Eliminative pluralism and integrative approaches: the case of species. Br J Philos Sci 70(3):657–681. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx057

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Born G (2010) For a relational musicology: music and interdisciplinarity, beyond the practice turn. J R Music Assoc 135:205–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Both AA (2009) Music archaeology: some methodological and theoretical considerations. Yearb Tradit Music 41:1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2003) Species pluralism does not imply species eliminativism. Philos Sci 70:1305–1316

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase P, Nowell A (1998) Taphonomy of a suggested middle Paleolithic bone flute from Slovenia. Curr Anthropol 39:549–553

    Google Scholar 

  • Conard N, Malina M (2008) New evidence for the origins of music from the caves of the Swabian Jura. In: Both AA, Eichmann R, Hickmann, E, Koch L-C (eds) Challenges and objectives in music archeology. Studien zur Musikarchäology VI, Orient-Archäologie 22. Verlag Marie Leidorf GmbH, Rahden, pp 13–22

  • Conard N, Malina M, Münzel S (2009) New flutes document the earliest musical tradition in southwestern Germany. Nature 460:737–740

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross I (2012) Cognitive science and the cultural nature of music. Top Cogn Sci 4:668–677

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie A (2016) The mystery of the Triceratops’s mother: how to be a realist about the species category. Erkenntnis 81:795–816

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie A (2019) Scientific knowledge and the deep past: history matters. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie A, Killin A (2016) Musical pluralism and the science of music. Eur J Philos Sci 6(1):9–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie A, Killin A (2017) Not music, but musics: a case for conceptual pluralism in aesthetics. Estetika 54(2):151–174

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Errico F, Lawson G (2006) The sound paradox: how to assess the acoustic significance of archaeological evidence? In: Scarre C, Lawson G (eds) Archaeoacoustics. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge, pp 41–57

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Errico F, Henshilwood C, Lawson G et al (2003) Archaeological evidence for the emergence of language, symbolism, and music—an alternative multidisciplinary perspective. J World Prehistory 17:1–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies S (2004) John Cage’s 4’33”: is it music? In: Davies S (ed) Themes in the philosophy of music. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 11–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies S (2012) On defining music. Monist 95:535–555

    Google Scholar 

  • Diedrich C (2015) ‘Neanderthal bone flutes’: simply products of Ice Age spotted hyena scavenging activities on cave bear cubs in European cave bear dens. R Soc Open Sci 2:140022

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimkaroski L (2014) Musical research into the flute. From suspected to contemporary musical instrument. In: Turk I (ed) Divje babe I. Upper Pleistocene Palaeolithic site in Slovenia. Part 2: archaeology. ZRC Publishing, Ljubljana, pp 215–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd J (2018) What 4’33” is. Australas J Philos 96(4):629–641

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (1992) Eliminative pluralism. Philos Sci 59:671–690

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (1998) Species pluralism and anti-realism. Philos Sci 65:103–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2001) The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: a philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2017) Species. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy (Fall 2017 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/species. Accessed 11 Jan 2019

  • Finlayson C (2009) The humans who went extinct: why Neanderthals died out and we survived. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Stotz K (2013) Genetics and philosophy: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Guilfoy K (2012) William of Champeaux. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/william-champeaux. Accessed 11 Jan 2019

  • Horner JR, Lamm ET (2011) Ontogeny of the parietal frill of Triceratops: a preliminary histological analysis. CR Palevol 10:439–452

    Google Scholar 

  • Kania A (2010) Silent music. J Aesthet Art Crit 68:343–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Kania A (2011) Definition. In: Gracyk T, Kania A (eds) Routledge companion to philosophy and music. Routledge, London, pp 3–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Killin A (2016) Rethinking music’s status as adaptation versus technology: a niche construction perspective. Ethnomusicol Forum 25(2):210–233

    Google Scholar 

  • Killin A (2017) Plio-Pleistocene foundations of hominin musicality: coevolution of cognition, sociality, and music. Biol Theory 12(4):222–235

    Google Scholar 

  • Killin A (2018) The origins of music: evidence, theory and prospects. Music Sci. https://doi.org/10.1177/2059204317751971

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) Species. Philos Sci 51(2):308–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson J (1990) Music, art, and metaphysics. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1978) Truth in fiction. Am Philos Q 15(1):37–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Longrich NR, Field DJ (2012) Torosaurus is not Triceratops: ontogeny in chasmosaurine ceratopsids as a case study in dinosaur taxonomy. PLoS ONE 7(2):e32623

    Google Scholar 

  • Maconie R (1990) The concept of music. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mag Uidhir C, Magnus PD (2011) Art concept pluralism. Metaphilosophy 42:83–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariorino L, Farke AA, Kotsakis T, Piras P (2013) Is Torosaurus Triceratops? Genomic morphometric evidence of late maastrichtian ceratopsid dinosaurs. PLoS ONE 8(11):e81608

    Google Scholar 

  • McKeown-Green J (2014) What is music? Is there a definitive answer? J Aesthet Art Crit 72(4):393–403

    Google Scholar 

  • Merriam A (1963) Purposes of ethnomusicology, an anthropological view. Ethnomusicology 7:206–213

    Google Scholar 

  • Merriam A (1964) The anthropology of music. Northwestern University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Mishler B (1999) Getting rid of species? In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 307–315

    Google Scholar 

  • Mithen S (2005) The singing Neanderthals. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Morley I (2006) Mousterian musicianship? The case of the Divje Babe I bone. Oxford J Archaeol 25:317–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Morley I (2013) The prehistory of music: human evolution, archaeology, and the origins of musicality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanella JB, Horner JR (2010) Torosaurus Marsh, 1891, is Triceratops Marsh, 1889 (Ceratopsidae: Chasmosaurinae): synonymy through ontogeny. J Vertebr Paleontol 30:1157–1168

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2015) Natural kindness. Br J Philos Sci 66(2):375–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor H, Vickers P (2017) Conceptual fragmentation and the rise of eliminativism. Eur J Philos Sci 7:17–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuniz C, Bernardini F, Turk I et al (2012) Did Neanderthals play music? X-ray computed micro-tomography of the Divje Babe ‘Flute’. Archaeometry 54:581–590

    Google Scholar 

  • Turk I (ed) (1997) Mousterian ‘bone flute’ and other finds from Divje babe I cave site in Slovenia. Založba ZRC, Ljubljana

    Google Scholar 

  • Turk I, Bastiani G, Blackwell BA, Horusitzky Z (2003) Putative Mousterian flute from Divje babe I (Slovenia): pseudoartefact or true flute, or who made the holes? Arheološki vestnik 54:71–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Turk M, Turk I, Dimkaroski L et al (2018) The Mousterian musical instrument from the Divje babe I cave (Slovenia): arguments on the material evidence for Neanderthal musical behaviour. L’anthropologie 122:679–706

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins J (2018) The reality of species: real phenomena not theoretical objects. In: Joyce R (ed) Routledge handbook of evolution & philosophy. Routledge, New York, pp 167–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA, Barker MJ, Brigandt I (2007) When traditional essentialism fails: biological natural kinds. Philos Top 35:189–215

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn T, Coolidge FL (2012) How to think like a Neandertal. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zilhão J, Angelucci DE, Badal-García E et al (2010) Symbolic use of marine shells and mineral pigments by Iberian Neandertals. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 107:1023–1028

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For comments on previous versions of the material I thank Adrian Currie, Marilynn Johnson, Brandon Polite, Jason Waller, Ellen Clarke and anonymous referees. I thank audiences at the 2018 Joint Conference of the South Carolina Society for Philosophy and North Carolina Philosophical Society at Winthrop University, the 2018 Joint Conference of the Australasian Association of Philosophy and New Zealand Association of Philosophers at Victoria University of Wellington, the 2018 workshop on Art, Evolution and Cognition at Macquarie University, Sydney, the 2019 American Society for Aesthetics Eastern Division Conference in Philadelphia, and the 2019 Ohio Philosophical Association Conference at Wittenberg University.

Funding

This study was not funded by any external Grants.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anton Killin.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I declare that I have no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human Participants and/or Animlas

No animal nor human subjects were used in this research.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Killin, A. Music Pluralism, Music Realism, and Music Archaeology. Topoi 40, 261–272 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09676-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09676-z

Keywords

Navigation