Skip to main content
Log in

Radical Interpretation and Logical Pluralism

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I examine Quine’s and Davidson’s arguments to the effect that classical logic is the one and only correct logic. This conclusion is drawn from their views on radical translation and interpretation, respectively. I focus on the latter, but I first address, independently, Quine’s argument to the effect that the ‘deviant’ logician, who departs from classical logic, is merely changing the subject. Regarding logical pluralism, the question is whether there is more than one correct logic. I argue that bivalence may be subject matter dependent, but that distribution and the law of excluded middle can probably not be dropped whilst maintaining the standard meanings of the connectives. In discussing the ramifications of the indeterminacy of interpretation, I ask whether it forces Davidsonian interpreters to adopt Dummett’s epistemic conception of truth vis-à-vis their interpretations. And, if so, does this cohere with their attributing a nonepistemic notion of truth to their interpretees? This would be a form of logical pluralism. In addition, I discuss Davidson’s arguments against conceptual schemes. Schemes incommensurable with our own could be construed as wholesale deviant logics, or so I argue. And, if so, their possibility would yield, in turn, the possibility of a radical logical pluralism. I also address Davidson’s application of Tarski’s definition of truth.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This example is similar to one suggested to me by Kirk Ludwig.

  2. In addition, of course, if we have reason to reject the manifestation principle, then we have reason to reject the private language and acquisition arguments that lead to it.

References

  • Brogaard B, Salerno J (2013) Fitch’s paradox of knowability. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2013 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/fitch-paradox/

  • Dalla Chiara M, Giuntini R, Greechie R (2004) Reasoning in quantum theory. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1984a) Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1984b) The inscrutability of reference. Reprinted in Davidson, 1984a, pp 227–241

  • Davidson D (1984c) On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Reprinted in Davidson, 1984a, pp 183–198

  • Davidson D (1984d) Radical interpretation. Reprinted in Davidson, 1984a, pp 125–139

  • Davidson D (1984e) On saying that. Reprinted in Davidson, 1984a, pp 93–108

  • Davidson D (1994) Radical interpretation interpreted. In: Tomberlin J (ed) Philosophical perspectives: logic and language, vol 8. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 122–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (2001a) Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (2001b) What is present to the mind? Reprinted in Davidson, 2001a, pp 53–68

  • Davidson D (2001c) Externalisms. In: Kotatko P, Pagin P, Segal G (eds) Interpreting Davidson. CSLI, Stanford, pp 1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (2005) Truth and predication. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • LePore E, Ludwig K (2003) Truth and meaning. In Ludwig K (ed) (ed) Donald Davidson. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 35–63

    Google Scholar 

  • LePore E, Ludwig K (2005) Donald Davidson: meaning, truth, language, and reality. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller A (2002) What is the manifestation argument? Pac Philos Quar 83:352–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller A (2016) Realism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2016 edn. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/realism/

  • Priest G (2001) An introduction to non-classical logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior A (1967) Past, present and future. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1986) Philosophy of logic, 2nd edn. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawling P (2003) Radical interpretation. In: Ludwig K (ed) Donald Davidson, contemporary philosophers in focus. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 85–112

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawling P (2013) Davidson’s measurement-theoretic analogy. In: LePore E, Ludwig K (eds) A companion to Donald Davidson. Wiley, New York, pp 247–263

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawling JP, Selesnick S (2000) Orthologic and quantum logic: models and computational elements. J Assoc Comput Machine 47(4):721–751

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ray G (2014) Meaning and truth. Mind 123:79–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt I (2015) The boundary stones of thought: an essay in the philosophy of logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell G (2016) Logical pluralism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2016 edn. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/logical-pluralism/

  • Sennet A (2013) Parataxis. In: LePore E, Ludwig K (eds) A companion to Donald Davidson. Wiley, New York, pp 191–207

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski A (1983) On the concept of logical consequence. In Corcoran J (ed) Logic, semantics and metamathematics, 2nd edn. Hackett, Indianapolis, pp 409–420

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason R (1970) Indeterminist time and truth-value gaps. Theoria 3:264–281

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1966) Singular terms, truth-value gaps, and free logic. J Philos 63:481–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1968) Presupposition, implication, and self-reference. J Philos 65:136–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson NL (1959) Substances without substrata. Rev Metaphys 12:521–539

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright C (1987) Realism, meaning and truth. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Piers Rawling.

Additional information

Many thanks to all those over the years who have educated me about Davidson’s views, by far the most helpful of whom was Donald Davidson himself. I also received helpful feedback from a reviewer for this journal. Errors are mine alone, of course.

Appendix: Fitch’s Paradox

Appendix: Fitch’s Paradox

Davidson’s requirement that speech and thought be interpretable (his version of the manifestation principle) might fall afoul of a version of Fitch’s paradox of knowability [for Fitch’s paradox, see Brogaard and Salerno (2013), and the references therein; see also Wright (1987), pp. 309–316]. On Davidson’s view, it must be possible for anything I mean by my utterances, or any propositional attitude that I have (including knowledge), to be known by an interpreter.

Let:

  • ‘K*p’ abbreviate ‘I know that p’

  • ‘Kp’ abbreviate ‘some interpreter of me knows that p’

  • ‘P’ abbreviate ‘it is possible that’

I’ll assume that the following are theorems for all propositions p, q:

  1. (1)

    Kp → p

  2. (2)

    K*p → p

I’ll also assume:

  1. (3)

    ‘K(p&q)’ and ‘(Kp&Kq)’ are intersubstitutable salva veritate in both extensional and knowledge contexts, as are ‘K*(p&q)’ and ‘(K*p&K*q)’ (so that, for example, ‘KK*(p&q)’ is true if and only if ‘K(K*p&K*q)’ is also).

and

  1. (4)

    If a proposition entails a contradiction, then it is not possible that the proposition be true.

According to Davidson, then,

  1. (5)

    For any proposition p: K*p → PKK*p

But he presumably allows that not all my states of knowledge are known to interpreters. [Davidson’s triangulation argument (see Davidson 2001c), I assume, merely purports to show that I have propositional attitudes only if some of them are known to interpreters of me, as opposed to purporting to show that all of my propositional attitude states are known to interpreters of me.] Furthermore, I know this. That is, there are propositions that I know to be true, and also know that no interpreter knows that I know to be true—I have at least some private knowledge that I know to be private.

Thus:

There is a proposition p such that: K*p&K*~KK*p.

Let q be such a proposition, so

  1. (6)

    K*q&K*~KK*q

By (3) and (6) we get:

  1. (7)

    K*(q&~KK*q)

(5) (substituting ‘q&~KK*q’ for ‘p’) yields:

  1. (8)

    K*(q&~KK*q) → PKK*(q&~KK*q)

Applying modus ponens to (7) and (8) yields:

  1. (9)

    PKK*(q&~KK*q)

But (9) is not true. ‘KK*(q&~KK*q)’ entails a contradiction (applying (3) to KK*(q&~KK*q) gives KK*q&KK*~KK*q, from whence we get KK*q&~KK*q by applying (1) and (2) to the right conjunct), and thus, by (4), ‘PKK*(q&~KK*q)’ is not true.

Hence we must abandon (5).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rawling, P. Radical Interpretation and Logical Pluralism. Topoi 38, 277–289 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9494-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9494-4

Keywords

Navigation