Skip to main content
Log in

Contextual Debiasing and Critical Thinking: Reasons for Optimism

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article I argue that most biases in argumentation and decision-making can and should be counteracted. Although biases can prove beneficial in certain contexts, I contend that they are generally maladaptive and need correction. Yet critical thinking alone seems insufficient to mitigate biases in everyday contexts. I develop a contextualist approach, according to which cognitive debiasing strategies need to be supplemented by extra-psychic devices that rely on social and environmental constraints in order to promote rational reasoning. Finally, I examine several examples of contextual debiasing strategies and show how they can contribute to enhance critical thinking at a cognitive level.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Despite mounting criticism, Meliorism remains the dominant position among philosophers and psychologists. See for example Elster (2007), Evans (2007), Kahneman (2011), Kenyon and Beaulac (2014), Stanovich (2011), Larrick (2004), Croskerry et al. (2013a), Tetlock (2005), Wilson and Brekke (1994).

  2. Taylor (1989, p. 237) explicitly acknowledges this aspect: “Unrealistic optimism might lead people to ignore legitimate risks in their environment and to fail to take measures to offset those risks”.

  3. See, for example, Aberdein (2010) and Cohen (2009).

  4. Psychologists distinguish between two kinds of cognitive illusions: motivational (or “hot”) biases, on the one hand, which stem from the influence of emotions and interests on cognitive processes, and cognitive (or “cold”) biases, on the other hand, which stem from inferential errors due to cognitive malfunctioning (Kunda 1990; Nisbett 1993).

  5. Cf. Fisher (2011, p. 4), Lau (2011, p. 2), Siegel (1988, p. 32).

  6. The “tools” metaphor can also be found in other approaches that stress the importance of non-cognitive (or extra-psychic) devices as means to promote rationality: Soll et al. (2015) refer to “debiasing tools”, Hogarth (2001) to “decision-making tools”, Elster (1989) to the “toolbox of mechanisms”, and Gigerenzer and Selten (2002) to the “adaptive toolbox”.

  7. See, for example, Kenyon and Beaulac (2014), Larrick (2004), Soll et al. (2015).

References

  • Aberdein A (2010) Virtue in argument. Argumentation 24(2):165–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ainslie G (2005) Précis of breakdown of will. Behav Brain Sci 28:635–673

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson C, Sechler E (1986) Effects of explanation and counterexplanation on the development and use of social theories. J Pers Soc Psychol 50:24–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arkes H (1981) Impediments to accurate clinical judgment and possible ways to minimize their impact. J Consult Clin Psychol 49:323–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arkes H (1991) Costs and benefits of judgment errors. Psychol Bull 110(13):486–498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brest P, Krieger L (2010) Problem solving, decision making and professional judgment. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Budden A, Tregenza T, Aarssen L, Koricheva J, Leimu R, Lortie CJ (2008) Double-blind review favours increased representation of female authors. Trends Ecol Evol 23(1):4–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (1981) Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? In: Adler J, Rips L (eds) Reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen D (2009) Keeping an open mind and having a sense of proportion as virtues in argumentation. Cogency 1(2):49–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Croskerry P, Singhal G, Mamede S (2013a) Cognitive debiasing 1: origins of bias and theory of debiasing. Qual Saf 22(2):58–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Croskerry P, Singhal G, Mamede S (2013b) Cognitive debiasing 2: impediments to and strategies for change. Qual Saf 22(2):65–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1985) Incoherence and irrationality. Dialectica 39(4):345–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dick Cheney’s Suite Demands (2006) Retrieved January 8, 2016, from http://www.thesmokinggun.com/file/dick-cheneys-suite-demands

  • Dunning D (2009) Disbelief and the neglect of environmental context. Behav Brain Sci 32:517–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1989) Nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (2007) Explaining social behavior. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engel P (ed) (2000) Believing and accepting. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans J (2007) Hypothetical thinking. Psychology Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischhoff B (1982) Debiasing. In: Kahneman D, Slovic P, Tversky A (eds) Judgment under uncertainty. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischhoff B (2002) Heuristics and biases in application. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher A (2011) Critical thinking: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky A, Moskowitz G, Gordon B (2000) Perspective taking. J Pers Soc Psychol 784:708–724

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G (2008) Rationality for mortals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Selten R (2002) Bounded rationality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Todd P (2000) Précis of simple heuristics that make us smart. Behav Brain Sci 23:727–780

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirt E, Markman K (1995) Multiple explanation: a consider-an-alternative strategy for debiasing judgments. J Pers Soc Psychol 69:1069–1086

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth R (2001) Educating intuition. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson R, Blair A (2006) Logical self-defense. International Debate Association, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenyon T, Beaulac G (2014) Critical thinking education and debiasing. Informal Log 34(4):341–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunda Z (1990) The case for motivated reasoning. Psychol Bull 108(3):480–498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larrick R (2004) Debiasing. In: Koehler D, Harvey N (eds) The Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau J (2011) An introduction to critical thinking and creativity. Wiley, New Jersey

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lilienfeld S, Ammirati R, Landfield K (2009) Giving debiasing away. Perspect Psychol Sci 4(4):390–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord G, Lepper R, Preston E (1984) Considering the opposite: a corrective strategy for social judgment. J Pers Soc Psychol 47:1231–1243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKay R, Dennett D (2009) The evolution of misbelief. Behav Brain Sci 32:493–561

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Sperber D (2011) Why do humans reason? Behav Brain Sci 34:57–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mussweiler T, Strack F, Pfeiffer T (2000) Overcoming the inevitable anchoring effect. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 26:1142–1150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers D (1975) Discussion-induced attitude-polarization. Hum Relat 28:699–714

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett R (ed) (1993) Rules for reasoning. Erlbaum, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford M, Chater N (2009) Précis of Bayesian Rationality. Behav Brain Sci 32:69–120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paluk E, Green D (2009) Prejudice reduction: what works? A review and assessment of research and practice. Annu Rev Psychol 60:339–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul W (1986) Critical thinking in the strong and the role of argumentation in everyday life. In: Eemeren F, Grootendorst R, Blair A, Willard C (eds) Argumentation. Foris Publications, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelham B, Neter E (1995) The effect of motivation of judgment depends on the difficulty of the judgment. J Pers Soc Psychol 68(4):581–594

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pronin E, Lin D, Ross L (2002) The bias blind spot: perceptions of bias in self versus others. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 28:369–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2000) Lectures on the history of political philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanna L, Schwarz N, Stocker S (2002) When debiasing backfires. J Exp Psychol 28:497–502

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel H (1988) Educating reason. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Soll J, Milkman K, Payne J (2015) Outsmart your own biases. Harv Bus Rev 93:65–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich K (2005) The robot’s rebellion. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich K (2011) Rationality and the reflective mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich K, West R (2008) On the relative independence of thinking biases and cognitive ability. J Pers Soc Psyshol 94:672–695

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein E (1996) Without good reason. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich S (1990) The fragmentation of reason. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C (2003) Why societies need dissent. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C, Schkade D, Ellman L (2004) Ideological voting on federal courts of appeal. Va Law Rev 90(1):301–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taber C, Lodge M (2006) Motivated skepticism in the evaluation of political beliefs. Am J Polit Sci 50(3):755–769

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor S (1989) Positive illusions. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor S, Brown J (1988) Illusion and well-being. Psychol Bull 103(2):193–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock P (2002) Intuitive politicians, theologians, and prosecutors. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock P (2005) Expert political judgment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock P, Boettger R (1989) Accountability. J Pers Soc Psychol 57:388–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard P (2011) Critical thinking and informal logic. Informal Log 31(3):152–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler R, Sunstein C (2008) Nudge. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (2008) Extensional versus intuitive reasoning. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Willingham D (2007) Critical thinking: why is it so hard to teach? Am Educ 31(2):8–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson T, Brekke N (1994) Mental contamination and mental correction. Psychol Bull 116(1):117142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson T, Centerbar D, Brekke N (2002) Mental contamination and the debiasing problem. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the editor and two anonymous reviewers for their constructive comments. Work on this article was conducted under the grant SFRH/BPD/101744/2014 by the “Portuguese Foundation for Science and Technology” (FCT), as part of the project “Values in argumentative discourse” (PTDC/MHC-FIL/0521/2014).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vasco Correia.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Correia, V. Contextual Debiasing and Critical Thinking: Reasons for Optimism. Topoi 37, 103–111 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9388-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9388-x

Keywords

Navigation