Skip to main content
Log in

Intertemporal choice with savoring of yesterday

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The problem of intertemporal choice arises when outcomes are received in different moments of time. This paper presents an axiomatic model of intertemporal choice when consumption in the previous moment of time contributes to utility evaluation of consumption in the current moment. This model generalizes classic discounted utility theory (also known as constant or exponential discounting) in two ways. First, in every moment of time, a decision maker derives utility not only from current consumption but also from “residual” consumption in the previous moment of time. Second, these utilities are discounted with weights that are essentially a quasi-hyperbolic discounting function. The paper presents an application of the proposed model to the problem of optimal consumption and savings given a fixed income (wealth). When a decision maker derives satisfaction from both instantaneous consumption as well as a share of consumption in the previous moment of time, optimal consumption path is cyclic—periods of relatively high consumption are interchanged with periods of relatively low consumption. These cycles decay over time. Asymptotically, the consumption path exhibits conventional properties (constant, increasing or decreasing over time when a gross interest rate multiplied by discount factor is correspondingly equal to, greater than, or less than one).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bleichrodt et al., (2008, p. 342) refer to this assumption as the first period sensitivity.

  2. The same effect is visible to a lesser extent on Fig. 3 as well.

  3. Many subjects also preferred a constant stream over increasing and decreasing streams.

References

  • Allais, M. (1953). Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulates et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baucells, M., & Sarin, R. K. (2007). Satiation in discounted utility. Operations Research, 55(1), 170–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G., & Murphy, K. M. (1988). A theory of rational addiction. Journal of Political Economy, 96(4), 675–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaschke, W., & Bol, G. (1938). Geometrie der Gewebe: Topologische Fragen der Differentialgeometrie. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2013). A simple behavioral characterization of subjective expected utility. Operations Research, 61(4), 932–940.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2016). A monotone model of intertemporal choice. Economic Theory, 62(4), 785–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2021). Intertemporal choice as a tradeoff between cumulative payoff and average delay. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 64, 89–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Rohde, K., & Wakker, P. (2008). Koopmans’ constant discounting for intertemporal choice: A simplification and a generalization. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 52, 341–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradford, D. W., Dolan, P., & Galizzi, M. M. (2019). Looking ahead: Subjective time perception and individual discounting. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 58, 43–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1954). Representation of a Preference Ordering by a Numerical Function. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Decision Processes (pp. 159–165). New York: John Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1960). Topological Methods in Cardinal Utility. In K. Arrow, S. Karlin, & P. Suppes (Eds.), “Mathematical Methods in Social Sciences” Stanford (pp. 16–26). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duesenberry, J. (1952). Income, Savings, and the Theory of Consumer Behavior. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, J., & Prelec, D. (2007). The fragility of time: Time-insensitivity and valuation of the near and far future. Management Science, 53(9), 1423–1438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality Cambridge. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O'donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40, 351-401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Killeen, P. R. (2009). An additive-utility model of delay discounting. Psychological Review, 116(3), 602–619.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, K., & Zauberman, G. (2009). Perception of anticipatory time in temporal discounting. Journal of Neuroscience, Psychology, and Economics, 2(2), 91–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling, V., & Wakker, P. P. (2003). Preference foundations for nonexpected utility: A generalized and simplified technique. Mathematics of Operations Research, 28, 395–423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28, 287–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krantz, D. H., Luce, R. D., Suppes, P., & Tversky, A. (1971). Foundations of Measurement, (Additive and Polynomial Representations) (Vol. 3). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D. (1997). Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 443–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (1987). Anticipation and the valuation of delayed consumption. Economic Journal, 97, 666–684.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (1988). Frames of mind in intertemporal choice. Management Science, 34, 200–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1992). Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an interpretation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 573–597.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1993). Preferences for sequences of outcomes. Psychological Revue, 100, 91–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Sicherman, N. (1991). Do workers prefer increasing wage profiles? Journal of Labour Economics, 9, 67–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magen, E., Dweck, C. S., & Gross, J. J. (2008). The hidden-zero effect: Representing a single choice as an extended sequence reduces impulsive choice. Psychological Science, 19, 648–649.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., Mariotti, M., & Mittone, L. (2010). Choosing monetary sequences: Theory and experimental evidence. Theory and Decision, 69, 327–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E., & Pollak, R. (1968). On second-best national saving and game-equilibrium growth. The Review of Economic Studies, 35, 185–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollak, R. A. (1970). Habit formation and dynamic demand functions. Journal of Political Economy, 78(4), 745–763.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, D., & Scholten, M. (2012). Tradeoffs between sequences: Weighing accumulated outcomes against outcome-adjusted delays. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 38(6), 1675–1688.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, K. E., & Heal, G. M. (1973). Optimal growth with intertemporally dependent preferences. Review of Economic Studies, 40, 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. (1937). A note on measurement of utility. The Review of Economic Studies, 4, 155–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. (1952). Probability, utility, and the independence axiom. Econometrica, 20(4), 670–678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholten, M., Read, D., & Sanborn, A. (2016). Cumulative weighing of time in intertemporal Tradeoffs. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 145(9), 1177–1205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, T. (2005). Loss of self-contol in intertemporal choice may be attributable to logarithmic time-perception. Medical Hypotheses, 65(4), 691–693.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H. (1981). Some empirical evidence on dynamic inconsistency. Economics Letters, 8, 201–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urminsky, O., & Kivetz, R. (2011). Scope insensitivity and the “mere token” effect. Journal of Marketing Research, 48, 282–295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (1984). Cardinal coordinate independence for expected utility. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 28, 110–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (1988). The algebraic versus the topological approach to additive representations. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 32, 421–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (1989). Additive Representation of Preferences, A New Foundation of Decision Analysis. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wathieu, L. (1997). Habits and anomalies in intertemporal choice. Management Science, 43(11), 1552–1563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wathieu, L. (2004). Consumer habituation. Management Science, 50(5), 587–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zauberman, G., Kim, K., Malkoc, S., & Bettman, J. (2009). Time discounting and discounting time. Journal of Marketing Research, 46, 543–556.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Pavlo Blavatskyy is a member of the Entrepreneurship and Innovation Chair, which is part of LabEx Entrepreneurship (University of Montpellier, France) and funded by the French government (Labex Entreprendre, ANR-10-Labex-11–01).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavlo R. Blavatskyy.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no relevant or material financial interests that relate to the research described in this paper.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

It is relatively straightforward to show that utility function (2) satisfies axioms 1–4. We shall prove only the sufficiency of these axioms. If all moments of time are null, then proposition 1 holds trivially by setting u(x) = 0 for any x (discount factors could be arbitrary). If only one moment of time t is nonnull, then there is a continuous utility function that represents preferences over outcomes in this nonnull moment of time (Debreu 1954, Theorem I, p.162). Proposition 1 is then satisfied by setting utility function (2) equal to this utility function and letting βt be strictly positive. If two moments of time are nonnull, then by setting s = t and w = y in Axiom 4 we obtain a hexagon or Thomsen-Blaschke condition (Wakker 1984, p.112): whenever \(a_{t} {\varvec{x}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(b_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\), \(a_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(c_{t} {\varvec{x}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\), and \(b_{t} {\varvec{z}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(a_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\) then \(a_{t} {\varvec{z}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(c_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\). Additively separable utility representation (2) is then due to Hauptzatz über Sechseckgewebe (Blaschke and Bol, 1938, p. 10; Debreu 1960) and Theorem 15 in Krantz et al. (1971, Section 6.11.2). If more than two moments of time are nonnull, then preference relation ≽ satisfies ordinal independence (\(a_{t} {\varvec{x}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(a_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\) implies \(b_{t} {\varvec{x}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)\(b_{t} {\varvec{y}}^{{\varvec{\alpha}}}\)) due to Lemma 2 in Blavatskyy (2013). Additively separable utility representation (2) is then due to Theorem 3 in Debreu (1960) and Theorem 15 in Krantz et al. (1971, Section 6.11.2).

Q.E.D.

3.1 Proof of Proposition 2

A preference relation ≽ satisfies axioms 1–4 if and only if it admits representation (2) due to Proposition 1. It is relatively straightforward to show that utility function (1) satisfies axiom 6. It remains to show that when preferences are represented by utility function (2) and Axiom 6 holds then they are indeed represented by utility function (1).

Let us consider two streams such that \(\left( {x_{0} , x_{1} , x_{2} ,x_{3} ,x_{4} \ldots , ,x_{T} } \right)\sim \left( {x_{0} , x_{1} ,y_{2} ,x_{3} ,x_{4} \ldots , ,x_{T} } \right)\). If preferences are represented by utility function (2) then this preference indifference implies

$$ \beta_{2} u\left( {x_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)\, + \,\beta_{3} u\left( {x_{3}^{\alpha } } \right)\, = \,\beta_{2} u\left( {y_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)\, + \,\beta_{3} u\left( {y_{3}^{\alpha } } \right) $$

which can be rearranged as

$$ \beta_{2} \left[ {u\left( {x_{2}^{\alpha } } \right) - u\left( {y_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)} \right] = \beta_{3} \left[ {u\left( {y_{3}^{\alpha } } \right) - u\left( {x_{3}^{\alpha } } \right)} \right] $$
(4)

If Axiom 6 holds, then we must also have \(\left( {x_{1} , x_{2} ,x_{3} , \ldots , ,x_{T} ,x_{0} } \right)\sim \left( {x_{1} ,y_{2} ,x_{3} , \ldots , ,x_{T} ,x_{0} } \right)\). If preferences are represented by utility function (2), then this preference indifference implies

$$ \beta_{1} u\left( {x_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)\, + \,\beta_{2} u\left( {x_{3}^{\alpha } } \right)\, = \,\beta_{1} u\left( {y_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)\, + \,\beta_{2} u\left( {y_{3}^{\alpha } } \right) $$

which can be rearranged as

$$ \beta_{1} \left[ {u\left( {x_{2}^{\alpha } } \right) - u\left( {y_{2}^{\alpha } } \right)} \right]\, = \,\beta_{2} \left[ {u\left( {y_{3}^{\alpha } } \right) - u\left( {x_{3}^{\alpha } } \right)} \right] $$

Dividing this equation by Eq. (4) yields result \(\beta_{3} = \beta_{2}^{2} /\beta_{1}\). Iterating the same argument for subsequent moments of time we obtain that \(\beta_{t} = \beta_{2}^{t - 1} /\beta_{1}^{t - 2}\) for all t ∊ {1, …, T-1}. Finally, since utility function is unique up to a positive affine transformation, we can divide by \(\beta_{0}\) to obtain the conventional normalization that utility in the current moment of time is not discounted.

Q.E.D.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blavatskyy, P.R. Intertemporal choice with savoring of yesterday. Theory Decis 94, 539–554 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09898-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09898-5

Keywords

Navigation