Skip to main content
Log in

The metaphysical issues in the social sciences and how social scientists debate them

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most philosophical work on social ontology continues to be done without much connection to social scientific concerns. This special issue, however, calls for attention to a naturalized metaphysics, one based on the best science we have. It follows that a naturalized social metaphysics should begin with the best social science available. In contrast with the physical sciences, however, the best social science is not so clear. Thus, this paper acquaints professional philosophers with some of the prominent metaphysical views extant in the social sciences; the ways that more philosophically oriented social scientists engage them; and how professional philosophers might contribute.

In particular, the paper covers several arguments especially relevant to a naturalized social metaphysics. One argument suggests that folk intuitions cannot be excluded from consideration. In fact, in the social sphere, it may be that scientific concepts not only cannot always trump folk conceptions but actually must be constrained by them. The paper further introduces arguments defending not only metaphysically real levels of being but also the metaphysical reality of the categories of social science. Finally, the paper will introduce an argument that beyond culture and individual agency, social being also includes structure as a distinct category.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Unlike sociology or anthropology, as a discipline, political science is more formally divided between political science and political theory. The political scientists tend toward empiricism and a more or less Humean approach to the discovery of statistical generalizations. When the political theorists engage in empirical work, it is typically critiques of political discourse and hence more qualitative, reflecting a mostly post-structural paradigm. Other fields, like communication, cultural studies, and management now also draw heavily on sociology and political science.

  2. My experience as a teacher of research methods at both the graduate and undergraduate levels is that ordinary folk have great difficulty articulating even what causality means, let alone espousing any deeper metaphysical notion of it.

  3. Certainly, many sociologists do tacitly think of action in terms of reasons as per the folk psychology articulated by Davidson. The claim here is that the articulation of such tacit knowledge rarely makes it into explicit sociological theory with the untoward consequences about to be detailed.

  4. Some rational choice theorists, usually considered methodological individualists, do acknowledge a stronger sense of structure in the third sense above (see Tsebelis 1988). And in fact the games of game theory so often used by rational choice theorists arguably themselves constitute structures in the third sense.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2018). A realist conception of truth. Cornell University Press.

  • Apel, K. O. (2003). The response of discourse ethics to the moral challenge of the human situation as such and especially today. Peeters.

  • Archer, M. S. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge University Press.

  • Archer, M. S. (1996). Culture and agency: The place of culture in social theory. Cambridge University Press.

  • Archer, M. S. (2013). Social morphogenesis and the prospects of morphogenetic society. In A. Marga-ret (Ed.), Social morphogenesis (pp. 1–24). Springer.

  • Bhaskar, R. (2009). Scientific realism and human emancipation. Routledge.

  • Bhaskar, R. (1998). The possibility of naturalism: A philosophical critique of thecontemporary human sciences. Routledge.

  • Bhaskar, R. (2008). A realist theory of science. Routledge.

  • Block, N. (2003). Do causal powers drain away? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 133–150.

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. J. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465–500.

  • Bloor, D. (2011). The enigma of the aerofoil: Rival theories of aerodynamics: 1909–1930. University of Chicago Press.

  • Benton, T. (2010). Philosophy of social science: The philosophical foundations of social thought. Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Camic, C. (1986). The matter of habit. American Journal of Sociology, 91(5), 1039–1087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). A dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press.

  • Cloud, D. L. (1994). The materiality of discourse as oxymoron. A challenge to critical rhetoric. Western Journal of Communication (includes Communication Reports), 58(3), 141–163.

  • Cloud, D. L. (2018). Reality bites: Rhetoric and the circulation of truth claims in US political culture. The Ohio State University Press.

  • Cohen, I. J. (1989). Structuration theory: Anthony Giddens and the constitution of social life. Macmillan International Higher Education.

  • Collins, H. M. (1982). Special relativism—The natural attitude. Social Studies of Science, 12(1), 139–143.

  • Collins, H. M. (1992). Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. Chicago University of Chicago Press.

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Agency. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Essays on actions and events (pp. 43-62). Clarendon.

  • Davidson, D. (2013). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series, 209–222.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. The journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (2015). Retrieving realism. Harvard University Press.

  • Durkheim, E. (1951). Suicide. Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2020). Pragmatism, critical realism, and financial value. SASE Finance & Society Network.

  • Emirbayer, M., & Mische, A. (1998). What is agency. American Journal of Sociology, 103(4), 962–1023.

  • Epstein, B. (2015). The ant trap: Rebuilding the foundations of the social sciences. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science.

  • Esfeld, M. (2018). Metaphysics of science as naturalized metaphysics. In A. Barberouse, D. Bonay, & M. Cozik (Eds.) The philosophy of science. A companion (pp. 142–70). Oxford.

  • Geertz, C. (1977). The interpretation of cultures. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groff, R. (2000). The truth of the matter: Roy Bhaskar’s critical realism and the concept of alethic truth. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 30, 407–435.

  • Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2016). Reduction and emergence in science and philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Harvard university press.

  • Harré, R., & Madden, E. (1975). Causal powers: Theory of natural necessity. Blackwell

  • Haslanger, S. (2016). What is a (social) structural explanation? Philosophical Studies, 173(1), 113–130.

  • Haslanger, S. (2017). Racism, ideology, and social movements. Res Philosophica, 94(1), 1–22.

  • Hedström, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010). Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 36, 49–67.

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2015). On defining institutions: rules versus equilibria. Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3), 497–505.

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992). Structural explanation in social theory. In D. Charles, & K. Lennon (Eds.). Reduction, explanation, and realism (pp. 97–131). Oxford Clarendon Press.

  • Jameson, F. (2020). The prison-house of language. Princeton University Press.

  • Kim, J. (2006). Emergence: core ideas and issues. Synthese, 151, 547–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2007). Causation and Mental Causation. In B. McLaughlin, & J. Cohen (Ed.). Contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind pp. 227–242. Basil Blackwell.

  • Kincaid, H. (2004). Are there laws in social science? Yes. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science (pp. 168–187).

  • Kincaid, H. (1990). Defending laws in the social sciences. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 20, 56–83.

  • Kincaid, H. (2017). Philosophy without borders, naturally: An interview with Harold Kincaid”. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, 10(1), 83–100.

  • Kincaid, H. (2008). Structural realism and the social sciences. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 720–731

  • Kitcher, P. (2002). On the explanatory role of correspondence truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64(2), 346–364.

  • Knight, A. (2022). Wigener’s friend depends on self-contradictory quantum assumptions ArXive.2202.0711.v1. https://arxiv.org/pdf/2202.07111.pdf.

  • Kontopoulos, K. M. (2006). The logics of social structure (No. 6). Cambridge University Press.

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Everything must go: Metaphysics naturalized. OUP Oxford.

  • Latour, B. & Woolgar, S. (2013). Laboratory life. Princeton University Press.

  • Latour, B. & Woolgar, S. (2007). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor network theory. Oxford University Press.

  • Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality. Routledge.

  • Lawson, T. & Morgan, J. (2021). Cambridge social ontology, the philosophical critique of modern economics and social positioning theory: An interview with Tony Lawson, part 1. Journal of Critical Realism, 20(1), 72–97.

  • Law, J. (2009). Actor network theory and material semiotics. In B. S. Turner (Ed.), The New Blackwell companion to social theory. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Lizardo, O. & Stoltz, D. S. (2018). Max Weber’s ideal versus material interest distinction revisited. European Journal of Social Theory, 21(1), 3–21.

  • Manley, D. (2009). Introduction: a guided tour of metametaphysics. Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, 1–37.

  • Martin, J. L. (2011). The explanation of social action. Oxford University Press.

  • McIntyre, L. (2018). Post-truth. MIT Press.

  • Melnyk, A. (2013). Can metaphysics be naturalized? And if so, how? In D. Ross, J. Ladyman, & H. Kincaid (Eds.), Scientific metaphysics (pp. 79–96). Oxford.

  • Mol, A. (2003). The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Duke University Press.

  • Morgan, S. L., & Winship, C. (2007). Counterfactuals and causal inference. Cambridge University Press.

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford University Press.

  • Murdock, G. P. (1951). British social anthropology. American Anthropologist, 53(4), 465–473.

  • O’Connor, T., & Churchill, J. R. (2010). Nonreductive physicalism or emergent dualism? The argument from mental causation. The waning of materialism, 261–279.

  • Porpora, D. V. (1983). On the prospects for a nomothetic theory of social structure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 13, 243–264.

  • Porpora, D. V. (1989). Four concepts of social structure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 19, 195–212.

  • Porpora, D. V. (1993). Cultural rules and material relations. Sociological theory, 212–229.

  • Porpora, D. V. (2015). Reconstructing sociology: The critical realist approach. Cambridge.

  • Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1940). On social structure. The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland, 70(1), 1–12.

  • Rubinstein, D., (1977). “The concept of action in sociology.” Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 7(2), 209–236.

  • Ritchie, K. (2013). What are groups? Philosophical studies, 166(2), 257–272.

  • Schutz, A. (1967). The phenomenology of the social world. Northwestern University.

  • Searle, J. (1970) Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press.

  • Smith, C. (2016). The conceptual incoherence of ‘culture’ in American sociology. The American Sociologist, 47(4), 388–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swidler, A. (2001). Talk of love: How culture matters. University of Chicago Press.

  • Tsebelis, G. (1988). Nested games: the cohesion of french electoral coalitions. British Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 145–170.

  • Wacquant, L. J. D. (1992) Toward a social praxiology: The structure and logic of Bourdieu’s sociology. In P. Bourdieu, & L. Wacquant (Eds.), Invitation to a reflexive sociology (pp. 1–60). University of Chicago Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2005). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank the editor and three anonymous referees for their helpful comments on previous versions of this paper.

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas V. Porpora.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Porpora, D. The metaphysical issues in the social sciences and how social scientists debate them. Synthese 200, 501 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03978-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03978-3

Keywords

Navigation