Skip to main content
Log in

Model robustness in economics: the admissibility and evaluation of tractability assumptions

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Lisciandra (2017) poses a challenge for robustness analysis (RA) as applied to economic models. She argues that substituting tractability assumptions risks altering the main mathematical structure of the model, thereby preventing the possibility of meaningfully evaluating the same model under different assumptions. In such cases RA is argued to be inapplicable. However, Lisciandra is mistaken to take the goal of RA as keeping the mathematical properties of tractability assumptions intact. Instead, RA really aims to keep the modeling component while varying the corresponding mathematical formulation. Thus, her argument concerning whether the associated mathematical properties of certain assumptions can be kept intact is irrelevant to the success of RA. Furthermore, we explicate and develop Lloyd’s account of “model robustness” (Lloyd 2015) to provide solutions to Lisciandra’s challenges. Our solutions are, namely, error analysis and independent empirical support. We conclude that although complex economic models do face potential dangers, there are solutions and robustness analysis need not be given up. (157).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. In particular, see Woodward’s (2006) derivational robustness.

  2. The epistemic import of a robust model, or of the results of a robustness analysis, are a matter of contention amongst philosophers of science (Lloyd 2010, 2015; Parker 2018; Weisberg 2006; Woodward 2006). We take a stance on this issue in Sect. 3 below, following Lloyd’s (2015) account of model robustness.

  3. Schupbach (2018) emphasizes the diversity of models (or methods or measurements) and their ability to discriminate between explanatory hypotheses. In both the derivational robustness case and in the model robustness framework, such diversity can be understood in terms of the differences between the \(Ai\) s, and in the model robustness case the different sources of evidential support add to this diversity. While Schupbach’s account is claimed to be completely general and all-encompassing, other work has shown it to instead be complementary to Lloyd’s model robustness (O’Loughlin, 2021).

  4. Recently it has been shown that, prior to John Tyndall’s experiments, Eunice Foote showed experimentally that greenhouse gases such as water vapor and CO2 would lead to “solar heating” (Huddleston, 2019).

  5. This is in the spirit of Lloyd’s own suggestion that her account may be fruitfully applied to complex modeling generally (Lloyd 2015, p. 59). A few key differences between economics models and climate models: the latter are often run on supercomputers (they are simulation models) whereas the former are not; the latter employ well understood physical principles whereas the former do not; economists often explicitly desire analytic solutions whereas climate scientists work with numerical results (spatiotemporal gridded data which are output by the models).

  6. Thank you to an anonymous reviewer for pushing us on this.

  7. Kuorikoski et al. specifically mention that different and possibly contradictory assumptions could be made regarding the specific form of customer preference. E.g., constant elasticity substitution functions entail the independence of prices from the fundamentals of the market, while quadratic utility functions entail the opposite, both of which are “literally false” (562).

  8. See also Mäki and Marchionni (2009).

  9. Note she also switched from “iceberg assumption” to “price function”. The latter is a deductive result of the former. See footnote 10 (below) for details.

  10. McCann (2005) aims “to explain the subtle nature of these iceberg properties”, namely the Samuelson function and the Krugman function. Although both aim at representing transport costs, the Samuelson iceberg transport cost function is essentially a step function, characterized by its discontinuity. In contrast, the Krugman function explicitly defines the iceberg transport cost as \({V}_{d}={V}_{o}{e}^{-\tau D}\), where \({V}_{d}\) and \({V}_{o}\) are values of goods at destination and origin respectively, \(D\) is the distance between destination and origin, and \(\tau \) is the decay parameter. Then McCann (2005) deduces three properties of a Krugman function: “the delivered price of the good is (i) convex with respect to the distance, (ii) directly proportional to the original price of the good, and (iii) the transport rate per ton-kilometre is independent of the quantity shipped” (311). These properties are clearly very different from the Samuelson function and some others. E.g., it is not difficult to imagine a geo-economic model that assumes transport economies of scale, meaning that, as the quantity of goods gets larger, the average transport cost per unit gets smaller, which is contradictory to (iii). Thus, McCann concludes that “[t]hese fundamental differences between the properties of the Krugman iceberg assumption and more traditional transport cost functions, therefore lead to something of a problem of interpretation and inference.” (321, emphasis added). Lisciandra seems to interpret McCann’s “problem of interpretation and inference” as a problem for robustness analysis, which is a mistake.

  11. Note that in a recent paper, Lehtinen (2018, p. 556) argues that Lloyd’s (2015) account is weakened “considerably” by the fact that specific model assumptions (that are false if taken literally) such as parameterizations in climate models, are mutually incompatible and thus cannot indirectly confirm the truth of the model output. However, Lehtinen’s account seems to rely on an artificial dichotomy between the falsity and truth of model assumptions. Moreover, Lehtinen portrays Lloyd’s account as being solely concerned with the truth of the model output in virtue of agreement between models. While we do not have the space to defend Lloyd’s account here, we do regard this as a mischaracterization of Lloyd’s account that is at odds with the above description.

  12. See Marchionni (2017) for another appeal to combining empirical strategies of model testing with derivational robustness analysis in economic models.

  13. Thank you to an anonymous reviewer for helping us think further about this issue.

  14. According to McCann (2005): “all of the available evidence suggests that delivered prices tend to be concave rather than convex with distance” (pp. 315–316).

  15. E.g., the greenhouse effect (see Hulme, 2009).

  16. Interestingly, transport costs in older geographical economies models were also supported empirically by various sources (McCann 2005, pp. 311–312).

References

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Lisa Lloyd, Stu Gluck, Evan Arnet, Ann Campbell, Shannon Abelson, Nancy Cartwright, other folks from Lloyd Lab, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful feedback and conversations on various drafts of this work.

Funding

No funding was received to support this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

The authors contributed equally to the article.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan Li.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

O’Loughlin, R., Li, D. Model robustness in economics: the admissibility and evaluation of tractability assumptions. Synthese 200, 32 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03608-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03608-y

Keywords

Navigation