Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Can thoughts be read from the brain? Neuroscience Contra Wittgenstein

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Wittgenstein wrote: “No supposition seems to me more natural than that there is no process in the brain correlated with associating or with thinking; so that it would be impossible to read off thought-processes from brain processes.” In general, he rejects what he calls “psycho-physical parallelism.” In Sect. 1, I explain Wittgenstein’s position on this topic and how his followers defend it. In Sect. 2, I argue against Wittgenstein, contending that there is “thought” in a wider sense and that it can be “manifested” without expression. Thought does not need to be ordinarily expressed or even expressible, and it can be read off from the brain, provided one has sufficient technology, data, and understanding of the subject’s interaction with the environment. In Sect. 3, I offer results from brain-science in support of my claims.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Hacker, 1996,192–238, Candlish, 2001, Hyman, 2011, and Wenzel, 2016. See PI 412 f.

  2. For illustration and explanation of “lack of surprise,” see Hyman, 2011, 459.

  3. Frege, 1918–1919, 69.

  4. See Klagge, 1989, 329.

  5. Malcolm, 1984, 101. Klagge, 1989, 341.

  6. Wittgenstein 1975, 242. Klagge, 2019, 197.

  7. Wittgenstein, 1992, 96. Klagge, 2019, 202.

  8. Klagge, 1989, 320.

  9. Bennett and Hacker, 2003, 2.

  10. Glock, 2001, 19.

  11. Teichmann, 2017, 18.

  12. Hacker, 2013, 392.

  13. Hacker, 2013, 376.

  14. Hacker, 2013, 356.

  15. Schröder, 1995, 139.

  16. Ibid., 148.

  17. Ibid., 144.

  18. Ibid., 145.

  19. Teichmann, 2001, 26. See PI 158.

  20. Teichmann, 2017, 28, my highlighting.

  21. Teichmann, 2017, 12.

  22. Ibid., 15.

  23. Thornton, 1998, 177.

  24. Malcolm, 1995, 193, quoting PI 445.

  25. McDowell argues that concepts go “all the way out,” and Kant already argued that the categories go “all the way down to appearance.” See Wenzel, 2005.

  26. Glock, 2015, 351.

  27. Poincaré in 1905 observed that there are two kinds of mathematical minds (deux sortes d’esprits), one “geometric,” the other “analytic.” He even said one was borne that way (Poincaré, 1970, 27).

  28. Hao Tang (2015) argues that interpreters of Wittgenstein underestimate the pre-conceptual and primitive instinctive, such as between mother and child, and the role they play in language development (127). I agree. But Tang still holds on to the idea of thought as inner speech (106) and I think this is too narrow.

  29. Jackendoff, 2012, 81.

  30. Jackendoff, 1992, 16.

  31. Ibid., 90.

  32. Hurlburt at al. 2017, 5.

  33. Ibid., 6.

  34. Ibid., 4.

  35. Varela, 1996, 341.

  36. Ibid., 61.

  37. Smallwood et al., 2012, 60.

  38. Ibid., 63.

  39. Tusche et al., 2014, 113.

  40. Ibid., 112.

  41. Karapanagiotidis et al., 2016, 272.

  42. Morton et al., 2021, 2762.

  43. Huth et al., 2016, 454.

  44. Ibid., 453.

  45. Ibid., 457.

  46. Wang et al., 2017, 3.

  47. Reber et al., 2019, (1)

  48. Ibid., (2)

  49. Ibid., 8.

  50. Horikawa et al., 2013, 639.

  51. Quiroga et al., 2014, 363.

  52. Makin et al., 2020, 575.

  53. Ibid., 575.

  54. Ibid., 579.

  55. Ibid., 580.

  56. Moses et al., 2019, 8.

  57. Ibid., 2.

  58. Fuster, 2013, 13.

  59. Ibid., 62.

  60. Ibid., 65.

  61. Ibid., 179.

  62. Monti et al., 2012, 33.

  63. Weineck et al., 2020.

  64. Ibid., 2.

  65. Ibid., 6.

  66. Hacker, 2013, 368.

  67. Schröder, 1995, 150.

  68. Teichmann, 2017, 15.

  69. See Hanfling, 1993.

  70. Schröder, 2001, 148.

Bibliography

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Blackwell

  • Candlish, S. (2001). “The Will.”. In Glock (Ed.), Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader (pp. 156–173). Blackwell

  • Frege, G. (1918–1919). Der Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung. Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus, 2, 58–77

  • Fuster, J. M. (2013). The Neuroscience of Freedom and Creativity: Our Predicative Brain. Cambridge University Press

  • Glock, H. J. (2001). “Wittgenstein and Quine: Mind, Language and Behavior.” In Schröder (2001), 3–23

  • Glock, H. J. (2015). “Propositional Attitudes, Intentional Contents and Other Representationalist Myths.”. In Moyal-Sharrock, et al. (Ed.), Mind, Language and Action (pp. 512–537). De Gruyter

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1996). Wittgenstein and the Will: Volume 4 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2013). The Intellectual Powers: A Study of Human Nature. Blackwell

  • Hanfling, O. (1993). ‘Thinking, a widely ramified concept’. Philosophical Investigations, 16/2, 101–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horikawa, T., et al. (2013). Neural Decoding of Visual Imagery During Sleep. Science, 340, 639–642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurlburt, R. T., et al. (2017). “Can Inner Experience Be Apprehended in High Fidelity? Examining Brain Activation and Experience from Multiple Perspectives.” Frontiers in Psychology8/43.

  • Huth, A., et al. (2016). “Natural speech reveals the semantic maps that tile human cerebral cortex.” Nature, 532, 453–458

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, J. (2011). “Action and the Will.”. In O. Kuusela, & M. McGinn (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein (pp. 451–471). Oxford University Press

  • Jackendoff, R. (1992). Languages of the Mind: Essays on Mental Representation. MIT

  • Jackendoff, R. (2012). A User’s Guide to Thought and Meaning. Oxford University Press

  • Karapanagiotidis, T., et al. (2016). Tracking thoughts: Exploring the neural architecture of mental time travel during mind-wandering. NeuroImage, 147, 272–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klagge, J. C. (1989). Wittgenstein and Neuroscience. Synthese, 78, 319–343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klagge, J. C. (2019). “Wittgenstein, Science, and the Evolution of Concepts.”. In J. Beale, & I. J. Kidd (Eds.), Wittgenstein and Scientism (pp. 193–208). Routledge

  • Malcolm, N. (1984). Ludwig Wittgenstein. A Memoir. Oxford University Press

  • Malcolm, N. (1995). Wittgensteinian Themes. Essays 1978–1989. Cornell University Press

  • Makin, J. G., et al. (2020). Machine translation of cortical activity to text with an encoder-decoder framework. Nature Neuroscience, 23, 575–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monti, M. M., & Osherson, D. N. (2012). Logic, language and the brain. Brain Research, 1428, 33–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, N. W., et al. (2021). Semantic Knowledge of Famous People and Places Is Represented in Hippocampus and Distinct Cortical Networks. The Journal of Neuroscience, 41/12, 2762–2779

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moses, D. A., et al. (2019). Real-time decoding of question-and-answer speech dialogue using human cortical activity. Nature Communications, 10, 3096

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1970). La Valeur de la science. Flammarion

  • Quiroga, R. Q., et al. (2014). Single-Cell Responses to Face Adaptation in the Human Medial Temporal Lobe. Neuron, 84, 363–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reber, T. P., et al. (2019). Representation of abstract semantic knowledge in populations of human single neurons in the medial temporal lobe. PLoS Biology, 17/6, 1–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Schröder, S. (1995). “Is Thinking a Kind of Speaking? Philosophical Investigations, 18/2, 139–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schröder, S. (Ed.). (2001). Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Palgrave Macmillan

  • Smallwood, J., et al. (2012). Cooperation between the default mode network and the frontal–parietal network in the production of an internal train of thought. Brain Research, 1428, 60–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tang, H. (2015). A Meeting of the Conceptual and the Natural: Wittgenstein on Learning a Sensation-Language. Synthese, 91/1, 105–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Teichmann, R. (2001). “The Functionalist’s Inner State.” In Schröder (2001), 24–35

  • Teichmann, R. (2017). Not a Something. Nordic Wittgenstein Review, 6/1, 9–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, T. (1998). Wittgenstein on Language and Thought: The Philosophy of Content. Edinburgh University Press

  • Tusche, A., et al. (2014). Classifying the wandering mind: Revealing the affective content of thoughts during task-free rest periods. NeuroImage, 97, 107–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3/4, 330–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J., et al. (2017). Predicting the Brain Activation Pattern Associated with the Propositional Content of a Sentence: Modeling Neural Representations of Events and States. Human Brain Mapping, 38/10, 4865–4881

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weineck, K., García-Rosales, F., & Hechavarría, J. C. (2020). Neural oscillations in the fronto-striatal network predict vocal output in bats. PLOS Biology, March 19, 1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel, C. H. (2005). “Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle? Peter Rohs und John McDowell” (Do the Categories Play a Role Already in Perception According to Kant? Peter Rohs and John McDowell), Kant-Studien 96/4, 407-426

  • Wenzel, C. H. (2016). “Wittgenstein and Free Will.”. In S. Rinofner-Kreidl, & H. A. Wiltsche (Eds.), Analytic and Continental Philosophy: Methods and Perspectives (pp. 47–62). De Gruyter

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical Investigations (PI), trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Blackwell

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1975). In C. Diamond (Ed.), Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics. Cambridge 1939. The University of Chicago Press

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Remarks on The Philosophy of Psychology (RPP), trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Two vols. Blackwell

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Philosophical Grammar. PG). Blackwell

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1992). In von G. H. Wright, & H. Nyman (Eds.), Letzte Schriften über die Philosophie der Psychologie II. Das Innere und das Äußere (1949-1951). Blackwell

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Paisley Livingston for many helpful suggestions along the way of writing, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Helmut Wenzel.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wenzel, C.H. Can thoughts be read from the brain? Neuroscience Contra Wittgenstein. Synthese 200, 183 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03504-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03504-5

Keywords

Navigation