Skip to main content
Log in

The problem of creation and abstract artifacts

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Abstract artifacts such as musical works and fictional entities are human creations; they are intentional products of our actions and activities. One line of argument against abstract artifacts is that abstract objects are not the kind of objects that can be created. This is so, it is argued, because abstract objects are causally inert. Since creation requires being caused to exist, abstract objects cannot be created. One common way to refute this argument is to reject the causal inefficacy of abstracta. I argue that creationists should rather reject the principle that creation requires causation. Creation, in my view, is a non-causal relation that can be explained using an appropriate notion of ontological dependence. The existence and the creation of abstract artifacts depend on certain individuals with appropriate intentions, along with events of a certain kind that include but are not limited to creations of certain concrete objects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Dodd (2000, p. 431), Katz (2000, p. 148) and Cameron (2012, p. 180) for arguments that are similar to No Creation.

  2. See Rosen (2020) and Caplan and Matheson (2004, pp. 117–122) for a critical examination of (A2).

  3. I am leaving aside the nominalist option (the rejection (A1)), for my purpose here is to defend creationism against the competing Platonist views about the entities in question.

  4. Creationist authors in the ontology of music do not explicitly share this assumption. However, the terminology they use; i.e. indication, selection, or determination to describe the act of musical creation is amenable to being interpreted as a causal relation [Levinson (1980, pp. 21–22), Howell (2002, p. 107) and Trivedi (2002, p. 78)]. Evnine (2009, p. 215; 2016, pp. 137–138) is one exception. He argues that one can act with respect to the matter without causally manipulating it. The composer’s work does not modify the sound structure in a causal manner but “involves selection and display.” Although different from mine, Evnine’s conception of creation is also based on the rejection of (A3).

  5. In all fairness, Mag Uidhir raises further problems with this alternative. I address these problems below.

  6. The use of ontological dependence in metaphysical theories goes back to Aristotle (Corkum 2008). More recent accounts of ontological dependence, such as Lowe’s, reveal a family of relations that can potentially explain the relation between sets and their members, wholes and their parts, holes and their hosts, tropes and their bearers, etc. (Koslicki 2013, p. 31).

  7. For comparative evaluations of these relations see Fine (1995), Correia (2005, 2008), Koslicki (2013), Hoeltje et al. (2013), Tahko and Lowe (2016), and Schnieder (2020).

  8. Thomasson has abandoned some of her claims about the metaphysical nature of dependence relations between abstract artifacts and the creative activities of their authors. In her more recent work, Thomasson argues that the artifactual theory of fiction she developed in Fiction and Metaphysics should be combined with her deflationary metaontology (Thomasson 2007, pp. 110–125; 2015a, b, pp. 258–262). Although I am sympathetic to her metaontological views, the argument of this paper does not require any commitment to a particular metaontological theory.

  9. Although see Fine (1995) and Koslicki (2013).

  10. For a discussion on different kinds of ontological dependence relations see Thomasson (1999, pp. 24–34), Correia (2008) and Koslicki (2013).

  11. Bennett (2017, pp. 71–83) argues that causation, along with grounding, composition, and realization, is what she calls a building relation. In her view, building relations as a unified family share certain central features such as directedness, necessitation and generativity. Notice that the proponent of No Creation needs to commit only to the generativity of causation.

  12. This characterization of causation relies on a common idea that causation is a productive relation. Since No Creation argument requires a productive or a generative conception of causation, I will ignore the problems and complications that come with this view. For a discussion of a productive notion of causation, see Psillos (2002, p. 6).

  13. Notice that an alternative account of non-causal creation that makes use of metaphysical grounding instead of modal existential dependence would be free of this problem. Bennett (2017, p. 12), Schaffer (2016, p. 82) and Trogdon (2018, p. 189) argue that grounding satisfies both conditions and thus it is a necessarily generative relation.

  14. Although controversial, the view that impure sets exist when their concrete ur-elements come into existence is quite common. Gideon Rosen attributes this view to David Lewis (Rosen 2020). For others who adopt a similar view see Dodd (2002, p. 397), Caplan and Matheson (2004, p. 123), Rossberg (2012, p. 63), Mag Uidhir (2013, p. 140).

  15. A similar distinction is made by Cray (2017, p. 291). Cray takes generation to be a broader notion and reserve creation for intentional generation of artifacts. Nothing in our discussion here depends on this terminological choice.

  16. For a similar view about fictional characters, see Thomasson (1999, pp. 25–42).

  17. I am assuming once again that composition is not identity.

References

  • Bennett, K. (2017). Making things up. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, S. (2010). The case against creationism about fictional characters. Philosophical Review, 119(3), 337–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2012). How to be a nominalist and a fictional realist. In C. M. Uidhir (Ed.), Art and abstract objects (pp. 179–196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B., & Matheson, C. (2004). Can a musical work be created? British Journal of Aesthetics, 44(2), 113–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corkum, P. (2008). Aristotle on ontological dependence. Phronesis, 53(1), 65–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2005). Ontological dependence and cognate notions. Munchen: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2008). Ontological dependence. Philosophy Compass, 3(5), 1013–1032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cray, D. Wesley. (2017). Abstract generationism: A reply to Friedell. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 75(3), 289–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, H. (1991). The creation problem. Topoi, 10, 209–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2000). Musical works as eternal types. British Journal of Aesthetics, 40(4), 424–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2002). Defending musical platonism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 42(4), 380–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evnine, S. J. (2009). Constitution and qua objects in the ontology of music. British Journal of Aesthetics, 49(3), 203–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evnine, S. J. (2016). Making objects and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Ontological dependence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95, 269–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Vickers, P. (2011). Are there no things that are scientific theories? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(4), 771–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. (2010). Artifacts. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer edn.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoeltje, M., Schnieder, B., & Steinberg, A. (Eds.). (2013). Varieties of dependence: Ontological dependence, grounding, supervenience, response-dependence (basic philosophical concepts). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. (2002). Types, initiated and indicated. British Journal of Aesthetics, 42(2), 105–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. J. (2000). Realistic rationalism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2013). Ontological dependence: An opinionated survey. In B. Schnieder, M. Hoeltje, & A. Steinberg (Eds.), Varieties of dependence: Ontological dependence, grounding, supervenience, response-dependence (basic philosophical concepts) (pp. 31–64). Munchen: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (1980). What a musical work is. The Journal of Philosophy, 77(1), 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mag Uidhir, C. (2012). Introduction: Art, metaphysics, and the paradox of standards. In C. M. Uidhir (Ed.), Art and abstract objects (pp. 1–26). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mag Uidhir, C. (2013). Art and art-attempts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2002). Causation and explanation. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2020). Abstract objects. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring edn.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossberg, M. (2012). Destroying Artworks. In C. M. Uidhir (Ed.), Art and abstract objects (pp. 62–86). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies, 173, 49–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2020). Grounding and dependence. Synthese, 197, 95–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, E. T., & Lowe, E. J. (2016). Ontological dependence. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (winter edn.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (1999). Fiction and metaphysics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2007). Ordinary objects. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2015a). Ontology made easy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2015b). Fictional discourse. In S. Brock & A. Everett (Eds.), Fictional objects (pp. 256–274). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivedi, S. (2002). Against musical works as eternal types. British Journal of Aeshtetics, 42(1), 73–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trogdon, K. (2018). Inheritance arguments for fundamentality. In R. Bliss & G. Priest (Eds.), Reality and its structure (pp. 182–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walters, L. (2013). Repeatable artworks as created types. British Journal of Aesthetics, 53(4), 461–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank anonymous referees for their useful comments. For their helpful feedback on earlier drafts, I am grateful to Asya Passinsky, Simon Evnine, James Miller, Ned Markosian, Friederike Moltmann, Damiano Costa, and Philipp Blum.

Funding

Funding was provided by Bogazici University Research Fund (Grant No. 10321SUP).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nurbay Irmak.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Irmak, N. The problem of creation and abstract artifacts. Synthese 198, 9695–9708 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02672-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02672-6

Keywords

Navigation