Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition

  • S.I.: Radical Views on Cognition
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We discuss various implications of some radical anti-representationalist views of cognition and what they have to offer with regard to the naturalization of intentionality and the explanation of cognitive phenomena. Our focus is on recent arguments from proponents of enactive views of cognition to the effect that basic cognition is intentional but not representational and that cognition is co-extensive with life. We focus on lower rather than higher forms of cognition, namely the question regarding the intentional and representational nature of cognition found in organisms simpler than human beings, because enactivists do not deny that more sophisticated cognitive phenomena are representational and involve content. After introducing the debate on the naturalization of intentionality (Sect. 2), we briefly review different varieties of enactivism and introduce their central claims (Sect. 3). In Sect. 4 we turn to radical enactivism in order to focus on the arguments for a thoroughly non-representational, enactive account of perception and basic cognition. In particular, we discuss three major issues: First, what is supposed to replace the representational analysis of perception in a radical-enactive explanation of perception? How does the enactive explanation of perception compare to the best scientific work on the neuroscience of perception? Second, what is—on an enactive account—the function of neural processing in the brain for the generation of perception if not to produce representations? This question is especially pressing since one implication of autopoietic enactivism (accepted by radical enactivists) is that even the simplest organisms, i.e. single-celled organisms, have cognitive capacities (Sect. 5). Since they lack brains and nervous systems, enactivists must specify the (possibly) unique contribution of the brain and nervous system in those animals who have them. In Sect. 5, we evaluate the advantages of an autopoietic–enactive approach to the naturalization of intentionality and end with a suggestion how cognition may relate to intentionality and representation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For recent updates see Montague (2010), Smortchkova et al. (2019) and Dolega et al. (2018).

  2. Further work in this area includes Anderson (2014) and the collection of papers edited by Wilson et al. at https://www.frontiersin.org/research-topics/1713/radical-embodied-cognitive-neuroscience.

  3. It is often stressed that Gibson shared with enactivists the hostility to mental representations in the explanation of perception. It should be said, however, that his theory did not address the mechanistic basis of perception in the brain at all.

  4. According to the recently popular predictive processing accounts, perception itself is a highly inferential process (Clark 2016; Hohwy 2013). On such accounts, it makes no difference whether we called the process inferential or visual, of course, because this comes down to the same thing. See Gallagher (2017, ch. 6), for critical discussion.

  5. This is true even if we take into account ‘soliciting affordances’ (Siegel 2014) which, so to speak, ‘pull’ actions out of us automatically.

  6. Alternatively, if we do not understand the phrase in terms of rigidity, it does not seem to be at odds with classical cognitivism: Of course, in a very general sense, the brain is at any given time set up to be set off in some way. Understood in this loose way, however, classical cognitivism seems to be explanatorily stronger (given that explanatory power is understood as how good an explanation is under the assumption that it is true (see Ylikowski and Kuorikoski 2008), since it offers an account of what the brain is doing once it is set off: it computes representations which carry information about how things stand in the world.

  7. One way to avoid this conclusion is to accept accuracy conditions that are not yet truth conditions. One obvious move could be to interpret these accuracy conditions in terms of non-conceptual content. Yet, given Hutto and Myin’s rejection of non-conceptual representations, it is not easy to see just how these accuracy conditions should be characterized within their framework.

  8. Bruner (1964) introduced the term”enactive representation” (which today has an ironic ring to it) and distinguished such representations from “iconic” and “linguistic” representations. He conceived of enactive representations as “appropriate skills necessary for sensorimotor acts, for organizing percepts, and for organizing our thoughts” (1964, p. 1) and argued that all our cognitive acts “depend upon techniques rather than upon wired-in arrangements in our nervous system”. By an enactive mode of representing Bruner denotes a kind of representation that cannot be decoupled from an appropriate motor act directed towards some object. Several segments of our environment, like bicycle riding, tying knots, aspects of driving etc., Bruner argues, “get represented in our muscles” (1964, p. 2); these are cases of “representation by action alone” (1964, p. 3). A more recent example from the literature is Milner and Goodale’s (1995) patient D.F. whose posting action of a letter can be very well explained in terms of such action-oriented or “enactive” representations.

  9. A problem we ignore here is that with respect to the metaphysics of perception (Drayson 2018), Hutto and Myin more or less face the choice between naive realism and the sense datum theory once they reject the intentional theory. Although they do not elaborate on this, passages indicating that perception is “world-involving” (Hutto and Myin 2017, pp. 60, 92) suggest they opt for naive realism. This would require them to provide a theory of illusory or non-veridical experiences, which is a notorious difficulty for proponents of naive realism. But such a discussion is beyond the scope of this paper.

  10. See Thompson (2018) for a brief discussion of the differences between his thoroughly autopoietic enactivism and the radical enactivism defended by Hutto and Myin.

  11. For a defense that also plants have cognitive abilities, see Maher (2017).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C. (2017). On (not) defining cognition. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1454-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. (2014). After phrenology. Neural reuse and the interactive brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artiga, M. (2016). Liberal representationalism: A deflationist defense. Dialectica, 70(3), 407–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2018). The evolution of cognition. A 4E perspective. In A. Newen, L. de Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of 4E cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourjade, M., Thierry, B., Call, J., & Dufour, V. (2012). Are monkey able to plan for future exchange? Animal Cgnition, 15(5), 783–795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit, reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874/1995). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell & L. L. McAlister, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Bruner, J. (1964). The course of cognitive growth. American Psychologist, 19(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo, P., & Friston, K. (2017). Predicting green: Really radical (plant) predictive processing. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 14, 2070096.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo Garzón, P., & Keijzer, F. A. (2011). Plants: Adaptive behavior, root brains, and minimal cognition. Adaptive behavior, 19, 155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representation. Synthese, 101, 401–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In A. Jokic & Q. Smith (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1997). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dally, J. M., Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2006). Food-caching western scrub-jays keep track of who was watching when. Science, 312, 1662–1665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (2011). Self comes to mind. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory Sense-Making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the CognitiveSciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Kinds of minds. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolega, K., Roelofs, L., & Schlicht, T. (Eds.). (2018) . Enactivism, representationalism, and predictive processing. Special Issue of Philosophical Explorations, 21(2).

  • Drayson, Z. (2018). Direct perception and the predictive mind. Philosophical Studies, 175(12), 3145–3164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief: Form, content, and function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2014). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 115–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, A. (2010). Directive minds: How dynamics shapes cognition. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction. Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 219–244). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. T. (2008). Nano-intentionality: A defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biology and Philosophy, 23, 157–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2018). Ecology of the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 535–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactive interventions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Other minds. The octopus, the sea, and the deep origins of consciousness. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanus, D., Mendes, N., Tennie, C., & Call, J. (2011). Comparing the performances of apes (Gorilla gorilla, Pan troglodytes, Pongo pygmaeus) and human children (Homo sapiens) in the floating peanut task. PLoS ONE, 6(6), e19555. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0019555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk-psychological narratives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of seeing. The scope and limits of visual cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790/1998). In Guyer (Ed.) Critique of the power of judgment, 2002. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kelly, S. D. (2002). Merleau-Ponty on the body: The logic of motor intentionality. Ratio, XV(new series), 376–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. (2011). Anti-representationalism: Not a well-founded theory of cognition. Res Cogitans, 2, 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, P. (2006). The biogenic approach to cognition. Cognitive Processing, 7(1), 11–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, C. (2017). Plant minds. A philosophical defense. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martens, J., & Schlicht, T. (2017). Individualism versus interactionism about social cognition. Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9499-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, R. (2007). The measure of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. G. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The Realization of the living. Boston studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 42). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes, N., Hanus, D., & Call, J. (2007). Raising the level: Orangutans use water as a tool. Biology Letters, 3, 453–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 281–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1995). Pushmi-pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200. AI, connectionism, and philosophical psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. (2010). Recent work on intentionality. Analysis, 70, 765–782.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., Umerez, J., & Ibañez, J. (1997). Cognition and life: The autonomy of cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34, 107–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2016). A mark of the mental. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2009). Out of our heads. Newyork: Hill and Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2014). The varieties of presence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: Approaches to mental representation (pp. 1–20). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1031.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, S. (1999). Vision. Photons to phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raby, C. R., Alexis, D. M., Dickinson, A., & Clayton, N. S. (2007). Planning for the future in western scrub jays. Nature, 445, 919–921.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2017). Must cognition be representational? Synthese, 194(11), 4197–4214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2018). Representation and mental representation. Philosophical Explorations, 22(2), 204–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlicht, T. (2018). Does separating intentionality from representation imply radical enactivism? Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1497. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2014). Exploitable isomorphism and structural representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 64(2), 123–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2014). Affordances and the content of perception. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Enactive understanding and motor intentionality. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, & G. Riva (Eds.), Enacting intersubjectivity: A cognitive and social perspective on the study of interactions (pp. 17–32). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J., Stephan, A., & Walter, H. (Eds.). (2011). Affektive intentionalität. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P. (1988). On the proper treatment of connectionism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11, 1–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smortchkova, J., Dolega, K., & Schlicht, T. (Eds.). (2019). What are mental representations?. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2013). Fictionalism about neural representations. The Monist, 96, 539–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world. The evolution of human cognition. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2018). Review of Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin, evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Notre Dame Philosophical Review, January 11, 2018.

  • Treisman, A. (1988). Features and objects: The fourteenth bartlett memorial lecture. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 40A, 201–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dijk, L., & Rietveld, E. (2017). Foregrounding sociomaterial practice in our understanding of affordances: The skilled intentionality framework. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1969. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsych.2016.01969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. V. (1997). The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky: Problems of the theory and history of psychology (Vol. 3). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. (2002). Life after Kant. Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wehner, R. (1999). Large-scale navigation. In C. Freksa (Ed.), Spatial information theory. Berlin: D. Mark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2008). Minimal representing: A response to Gallagher. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16(3), 371–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, A., Golonka, S., & Barrett, I. (Eds.). Radical embodied cognitive neuroscience. Frontiers in Psychology. https://www.frontiersin.org/research-topics/1713/radical-embodied-cognitive-neuroscience. Accessed 6 Sept 2019.

  • Ylikowski, P., & Kuorikoski, J. (2008). Dissecting explanatory power. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9324-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article was supported by the project “The structure and development of Understanding actions and reasons”, funded by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (SCHL 588/3-1) and by the Volkswagen Foundation’s funding for the project “Situated Cognition. Perceiving the world and understanding other minds” (Az. 87 105). We are grateful for this support and want to thank two anonymous reviewers for valuable comments on an earlier version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobias Schlicht.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schlicht, T., Starzak, T. Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition. Synthese 198 (Suppl 1), 89–113 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02361-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02361-z

Keywords

Navigation