Skip to main content
Log in

Ought the State Use Non-Consensual Treatment to Restore Trial Competence?

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The important question of the legality of the state obliging trial incompetent defendants to receive competency-restoring treatment against their wishes, is one that has received much attention by legal scholars. Surprisingly, however, little attention has been paid to the, in many ways more fundamental, moral question of whether the state ought to administer such treatments. The aim of this paper is to start filling this gap in the literature. I begin by offering some reasons for thinking it morally acceptable to, at least sometimes, oblige trial-incompetent defendants to receive competency-restoring treatments. The paper then discusses whether three prominent arguments (and their variations) offered by legal scholars against using non-consensual treatment to restore trial competence provide grounds for thinking there to be a general moral prohibition against these treatments. I argue that they do not.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a notable exception, see Ryberg (2016). It is, however, worth noting that recently related questions regarding the ethics of using non-consensual treatments for the purpose of criminal rehabilitation have received much attention (see e.g. J. C. Bublitz and Merkel 2014; Douglas 2014; Focquaert 2014; Shaw 2014; Birks and Douglas 2018; Petersen 2018; Ryberg 2020; Holmen 2022).

  2. Throughout the paper I intend the term moral bad(s) to work as a placeholder for all of the the morally problematic aspects produced by an act. In relation to the specific example of civil confinement, the moral bad(s) may, for example, be the restriction of the defendant’s rights and/or the reduction in welfare that he may experience from the confinement.

  3. But for a critique of these reasons, see Ryberg (2016).

  4. Throughout the paper, following Kagan (1998), I use violate or violation to indicate that a moral right/value is set aside unjustifiably, and I will use infringe or infringement as an indicator of a morally permissible disregard or setting aside of the right/value.

  5. I thank a reviewer for pressing me to consider this. As the reviewer also noted another consideration that would prove non-consensual treatment to restore trial competence to be morally dubious would be if legal punishment as such (or the specific sanction the defendant faces) is morally unjustifiable. This is, I think, correct. Hence, I shall assume for the remainder of the paper that legal punishment in some form can be morally justified.

  6. The same, I believe, would arguably be true of treatments that, while leaving the defendant fully restored to trial competence, were also designed to make predictable changes in his preferences or attitudes that made him much more likely to admit his guilt. I thank a reviewer for suggesting I consider such treatments.

  7. Indeed, Feeman presents her view on the back of an analysis of Riggins v. Nevada, where the defendant, David Riggins, was found competent to stand trial despite being heavily sedated due to treatment with antipsychotic medication.

  8. For similar views see also Feeman (1993), Morse (2003), Annas (2004) and Perry (2017).

  9. To be clear, this is not to suggest that civil confinement is always as morally bad (or worse) than state punishment. Rather, the point is that in some cases it plausibly will be and, thus, in these cases it would arguably be morally better to non-consensually restore the defendant to trial competence even if this would lead to a biased trial.

  10. The scope of this objection will vary depending on whether one believes that (i) doling out both more severe sanctions and less severe sanctions than justice demands is morally problematic, or (ii) that only more severe sanctions than justice demands are morally unacceptable. Either way, however, the challenges I raise shortly would seem to stand, although they would have most force against (i).

  11. Although it may, of course, be wrong for other reasons. It may, for example, sometimes not be in the best interests of the non-autonomous defendant to receive the treatment. However, it would seem too strong to claim that treatment to restore trial competence can never be in a medical- and legal-incompetent defendant’s best interests: suppose, for instance, that the defendant, should he remain incompetent, is certain to be civilly confined for a prolonged period of time. Suppose further that if his trial competence is restored, he is likely to be found not guilty at his trial. It is not clear, at least in my view, that the former rather than the latter outcome would be in the defendant’s best interest.

  12. For a similar argument as regards to moral weight of autonomy in the context of using non-consensual neurological interventions to rehabilitate criminal offenders, see Ryberg (2020).

  13. Notice that I here use the term enhancement in a non-technical sense. That is, in the present context I intend it to merely mean that a cognitive ability is functioning better than prior to the intervention.

  14. Note that I here only claim that such autonomy-based reasons seem to exist, not that enhancing a defendant’s future autonomy in this way suffices to justify infringing the defendant’s present autonomy. This is a complicated and controversial question, a full examination of which requires more space than I can devote to it here.

  15. See also Bublitz and Merkel (2014) for a similar distinction between direct and indirect means of altering minds.

  16. Notice that the relevant difference between them cannot be that direct treatments are intended to alter the mind of the defendant while the mind-altering effects of indirect treatments are not so intended, a suggestion which has been offered to explain the putative morally relevant difference between the mind-altering effects of incarceration and rehabilitative neurointerventions (Birks and Buyx 2018). Both types of treatment scheme would obviously have as an aim to restore the defendant to trial competence and could presumably only do so by altering some part(s) of the defendant’s mental life.

References

  • American Psychological Association. 2002. Sell v United States, No. 02-5664..

  • Annas, George J. 2004. Forcible medication for courtroom competence: The case of Charles Sell. New England Journal of Medicine 350: 2297–2301. https://doi.org/10.1056/nejmlim033389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, Andrew, and Mike Redmayne. 2010. The criminal process. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2009. Principles of biomedical ethics. 6th edn. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benforado, Adam. 2015. Unfair: The new science of criminal injustice. New York: Crown Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, Christopher. 2018. Intrusive intervention and opacity respect. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, eds. David Birks, and Thomas Douglas, 255–273. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, David, and Alena Buyx. 2018. Punishing intentions and neurointerventions. AJOB Neuroscience 9: 133–143. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2018.1496162.

  • Birks, David, and Thomas Douglas. 2018. Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Boire, R. 2000. On cognitive liberty. Journal of Cognitive Liberties 1: 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boire, Richard G. 2002. Sell v. United States of America. Brief Amicus Curiae of the Center for Cognitive Liberty & Ethics in support of the petition.

  • Bostrom, Nick, and Anders Sandberg. 2009. Cognitive enhancement: Methods, ethics, regulatory challenges. Science and Engineering Ethics 15: 311–341. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-009-9142-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz, Christoph. 2016. Moral enhancement and mental freedom. Journal of Applied Philosophy 33: 88–106. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz, Christoph. 2018. 'The soul is the prison of the body’: Mandatory moral enhancement, punishment and rights against neuro-rehabilitation. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, eds. David Birks and Thomas Douglas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bublitz, Jan, Christoph, and Reinhard Merkel. 2014. Crimes against minds: On mental manipulations, harms and a human right to mental self-determination. Criminal Law and Philosophy 8: 51–77. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9172-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bullock, Jennifer Leslie. 2002. Involuntary treatment of defendants found incompetent to stand trial. Journal of Forensic Psychology Practice 2: 1–33. https://doi.org/10.1300/J158v02n04_01.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, Jared N. 2016. Incarceration, direct brain intervention, and the right to mental integrity: A reply to Thomas Douglas. Neuroethics 9:107–118. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-016-9255-x.

  • Dias, Aaron R. 2004. Just say yes: Sell v. United States and inadequate limitations on the forced medication of defendants in order to render competence for. South Carolina Law Review: 1–14.

  • Douglas, Thomas. 2014. Criminal rehabilitation through medical intervention: Moral liability and the right to bodily integrity. The Journal of Ethics 18: 101–122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-014-9161-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, Thomas. 2018. Neural and environmental modulation of motivation: What’s the moral difference? In Treatment for Crime 1–27. Oxford University Press.

  • Douglas, Thomas. 2022. If nudges treat their targets as rational agents, nonconsensual neurointerventions can too. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 25: 369-384. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10285-w.

  • Farah, Martha J. 2002. Emerging ethical issues in neuroscience. Nature Neuroscience 5.

  • Feeman, V. L. 1993. Reassessing forced medication of criminal defendants in light of Riggins v. Nevada. Boston College Law Review 35.

  • Focquaert, F. 2014. Mandatory neurotechnological treatment: Ethical issues. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 35: 59–72. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-014-9276-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogel, Michael H., Wendy Schiffman, Denise Mumley, Chad Tillbrook, and Thomas Grisso. 2013. Ten year research update (2001–2010): Evaluations for competence to stand trial (adjudicative competence). Behavioral Sciences & The Law 31: 165–191. https://doi.org/10.1002/bsl.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerbasi, Joan B., and Charles L. Scott. 2004. Sell v. US: Involuntary medication to restore trial competency: A workable standard? Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 32: 83–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glannon, Walter. 2019. The neuroethics of memory: From total recall to oblivion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, John R. 2004. Sell v. United States: Is competency enough to forcibly medicate a criminal defendant? Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 94: 657–686. https://doi.org/10.2307/3491394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmen, Sebastian Jon. 2022. Cognitive diminishments and crime prevention: 'Too smart for the rest of us’? Neuroethics 15: 1. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-022-09488-w

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ienca, Marcello, and Roberto Andorno. 2017. Towards new human rights in the age of neuroscience and neurotechnology. Life Sciences Society and Policy. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40504-017-0050-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, Shelly. 1998. Normative ethics. Dimensions of philosophy series. Oxford: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus & Giroux.

  • Karagianis, James, Benoit H. Mulsant, Ian Dawe, Rajiv Bhatla, and O’Reilly Richard. 2017. Too sick for freedom, too healthy for treatment. Untreated patients in forensic psychiatry: A literature review. Journal of Medical Law and Ethics 5: 81–103. https://doi.org/10.7590/221354017x14994239140324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladds, B., and A. Convit. 1994. Involuntary medication of patients who are incompetent to stand trial: A review of empirical studies. Bulletin of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 22: 519–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morse, Stephen J. 2003. Involuntary competence. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 21: 311–328. https://doi.org/10.1002/bsl.538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossman, Douglas, Stephen G. Noffsinger, Peter Ash, Richard L. Frierson, Joan Gerbasi, Maureen Hackett, and Catherine F. Lewis, et al. 2007. AAPL practice resource for the forensic psychiatric evaluation of competence to stand trial. The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 35: 3–72. https://doi.org/10.29158/JAAPL.003781-18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, Ashley. 2017. Retributive medication: A discussion of a Maine law allowing involuntary, forcible medication of a pretrial defendant for the purpose of rendering the defendant competent to stand trial. Maine Law Review 69: 137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, T. S., and K. Kragh. 2017. Should violent offenders be forced to undergo neurotechnological treatment? A critical discussion of the 'freedom of thought’ objection. Journal of Medical Ethics 43: 30–34. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103492. Department of Communication and Arts, Roskilde University, Roskilde, Denmark.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, Thomas Søbirk. 2018. Should neurotechnological treatments offered to offenders always be in their best interests? Journal of Medical Ethics 44: 32–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pirelli, Gianni, William H. Gottdiener, and Patricia A. Zapf. 2011. A meta-analytic review of competency to stand trial research. Psychology Public Policy and Law 17: 1–53. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0021713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, Stephen, Leanne ten Brinke, and Chantal Gustaw. 2010. Dangerous decisions: The impact of first impressions of trustworthiness on the evaluation of legal evidence and defendant culpability. Psychology Crime and Law 16: 477–491. https://doi.org/10.1080/10683160902926141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryberg, Jesper. 2016. Compulsory medication, trial competence, and penal theory. Law Ethics and Philosophy 4: 61–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryberg, Jesper. 2020. Neurointerventions, crime, and punishment: Ethical considerations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg, Anders. 2011. Cognitive enhancement cognition enhancement: Upgrading the brain. In Enhancing human capacities, 71–91. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, G., Guy Owen, Kahane, and Julian Savulescu. 2014. Autonomy and enhancement. Neuroethics 7: 123–136. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-013-9189-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz, Elizabeth G. 2005. Selling your soul to the courts: Forced medication to achieve trial competency in the wake of sell v. United States. Akron Law Review 503.

  • Schwalbe, Evan, and Alice Medalia. 2007. Cognitive dysfunction and competency restoration: Using cognitive remediation to help restore the unrestorable. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 35: 518–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, Elizabeth. 2014. Direct brain interventions and responsibility enhancement. Criminal Law and Philosophy 8: 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9152-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, Elizabeth. 2018. Against the mandatory use of neurointerventions. In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, eds. David Birks, and Thomas Douglas. Oxford: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, Joseph R. 2016. When restoration fails: One state’s answer to the dilemma of permanent incompetence. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 44: 171–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sparrow, Robert. 2014. Better living through chemistry? A reply to Savulescu and Persson on ‘moral enhancement’. Journal of Applied Philosophy 31: 23–32. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittemore, Karen E., and James R. P. Ogloff. 1995. Factors that influence jury decision making: Disposition instructions and mental state at the time of the trial. Law and Human Behavior 19: 283–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Stanley P. 2018. Double-blind justice: A scientific solution to criminal bias in the courtroom. Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality 6.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author thanks Jesper Ryberg, Thomas Søbirk Petersen, Frej Klem Thomsen, Emil Junge Busch, Cecilia Vollmer and two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Funding

No funds, grants or other support was received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sebastian Jon Holmen.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Holmen, S.J. Ought the State Use Non-Consensual Treatment to Restore Trial Competence?. Res Publica 29, 111–127 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-022-09563-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-022-09563-2

Keywords

Navigation