Skip to main content
Log in

Value Pluralism, Realism and Pessimism

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Value pluralists see themselves as philosophical grown-ups. They profess to face reality as it is and accept resultant pessimism, while criticising their monist rivals for holding on to the naïve idea that the right, the good and the beautiful are ultimately harmonisable with each other. The aim of this essay is to challenge this self-image of value pluralists. Notwithstanding its usefulness as a means of subverting monist dominance, I argue that the self-image has the downside of obscuring various theoretical positions that do not fall into either the pluralist or monist camp. Yet such positions do exist, as shown by my discussion of Albert Camus and Hannah Arendt. Near contemporaries of the pioneering value pluralist Isaiah Berlin, the pair, just like him, sought to be realistic about the lived experiences of political disasters and moral disorientation in the twentieth century. Moreover, they shared with Berlin a keen interest in real-world moral dilemmas, which seemed to them (as well as to Berlin) to have made traditional morality obsolete. But the three thinkers’ perspectives on ‘reality’ hardly converged, and neither Camus nor Arendt became a value pluralist as a result of their reflections on moral dilemmas. This, however, by no means indicates the pair’s immaturity. Rather, it shows that there is more than one way of observing fidelity to our actual experience and that value pluralists’ commitment to realism and resultant pessimism is not as uniquely mature as they would have us believe.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this essay I use the term ‘pluralism’ to mean value pluralism. Although Arendt may be called ‘pluralist’ in some other senses (see Flathman 2005), she certainly did not endorse value pluralism (or monism, for that matter). She never took sides in the pluralism/monism debate partly because she died in 1975, a few years before this debate emerged as an important issue in Anglophone philosophy. It is interesting to speculate on what she might have said had she lived two more decades and familiarised herself with the value pluralism/monism debate. As a matter of fact, however, this debate was unknown to her and the pluralism/monism rivalry remained alien to her thought.

  2. Needless to say, this does not necessarily mean that Arendt was more realistic than Berlin and Camus. Who among the three was most pessimistic is one question; whose stance on pessimism was most realistic is another. This essay is concerned with the first question. (Parenthetically, the second question cannot be answered on a general level because different contexts demand different levels of pessimism.)

  3. I use the term ‘existentialism’ in a broad sense to include Camus without minimising his disagreement with other existentialist figures such as Sartre.

  4. Arendt also discusses moral dilemmas in Eichmann in Jerusalem (Arendt 1965), which has attracted intense debate. A full discussion of this issue is beyond the scope of this essay, although I shall mention it briefly later.

  5. I follow the important distinction, introduced by Trunk (1996, pp. 570–575), between semi-voluntary ‘collaboration’ and thoroughly coercive ‘cooperation’. Berlin’s discussion here strictly concerns cooperation.

  6. This, according to Caute (2013, p. 270), was ‘one of Berlin’s favourite topics for light-hearted debate’.

  7. Berlin subscribes to this moralistic reading of Arendt, as evidenced by Berlin and Lukes (1998, pp. 107–108). Whether this reading is correct has been a central issue in the so-called ‘Eichmann controversy’. For further discussion see my forthcoming book provisionally entitled ‘Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin’.

  8. The mother’s consequentialist reasoning is also omitted in another telling of the story in The Rebel (Camus 2000, p. 134).

  9. This, needless to say, is the title of the French translation of Arendt’s The Human Condition.

  10. Isaiah Berlin to Miriam Gross, 26 November 1993. Oxford, Bodleian Library, MS Berlin 239, fols. 195–196; cited here with the permission of the trustees of Isaiah Berlin Literary Trust.

  11. I mean the final two chapters of the third edition of Origins, that is, ‘Totalitarianism in Power’ and ‘Ideology and Terror’, the latter originally published as Arendt (1953).

References

  • Aharony, Michal. 2015. Hannah Arendt and the limits of total domination: The Holocaust, plurality and resistance. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1953. Ideology and terror: A novel form of government. The Review of Politics 15: 303–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1965. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A report on the banality of evil, rev ed. New York: The Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1968. Between past and future: Eight exercises in political thought, expanded edn. New York: The Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1973. The origins of totalitarianism, 3rd edn. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1994. Essays in understanding 19301954. Ed. Jerome Kohn. New York: Schocken Books.

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2003. Responsibility and judgement. Ed. Jerome Kohn. New York: Schocken Books.

  • Baehr, Peter. 2010. Hannah Arendt, totalitarianism, and the social sciences. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2018. Exile, statelessness, and migration: Playing chess with history from Hannah Arendt to Isaiah Berlin. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2002. Liberty. Ed. Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2004. The Soviet mind. Ed. Henry Hardy. Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution Press.

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2013a. Against the current: Essays in the history of ideas. Ed. Henry Hardy. 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2013b. Concepts and categories: Philosophical essays. Ed. Henry Hardy. 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2013c. The crooked timber of humanity: Chapters in the history of ideas. Ed. Henry Hardy. 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2015. Affirming: Letters 19751997. Eds Henry Hardy and Mark Pottle. London: Chatto & Windus.

  • Berlin, Isaiah, and Steven Lukes. 1998. Isaiah Berlin in conversation with Steven Lukes. Salmagundi 120: 52–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brun, Georg. 2017. Thought experiments in ethics. In The Routledge companion to thought experiments, eds Michael T. Stuart, Yiftach Fehige, and James Robert Brown. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, Albert. 1946–47. The human crisis. Trans. Lionel Abel. Twice a Year 14/15: 19–33.

  • Camus, Albert. 1966. Carnets 19421951. Trans. Philip Thody. London: Hamish Hamilton.

  • Camus, Albert. 2000. The rebel. Trans. Anthony Bower. London: Penguin Classics.

  • Camus, Albert. 2004. The Plague, The Fall, Exile and the Kingdom, and selected essays. London: Everyman’s Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caute, David. 2013. Isaac and Isaiah: The covert punishment of a Cold War heretic. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, George. 2002. Liberalism and value pluralism. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, George. 2004. Isaiah Berlin: Liberty and pluralism. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dante. 1996. The divine comedy of Dante Alighieri, volume 1: Inferno. Trans. Robert M. Durling. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davis, Michael. 2012. Imaginary cases in ethics: A critique. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 26: 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flathman, Richard E. 2005. Pluralism and liberal democracy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, Philippa. 1967. The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review 5: 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William A. 2002. Liberal pluralism: The implications of value pluralism for political theory and practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gerassi, John. 2009. Talking with Sartre: Conversations and debates. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John. 2000. Two faces of liberalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John. 2013. Isaiah Berlin, new edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayden, Patrick. 2016. Camus and the challenge of political thought: Between despair and hope. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, Jeffrey. 1992. Arendt, Camus, and modern rebellion. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ishiguro, Kazuo, and Sue Lawley. 2002. Desert Island Discs. BBC Radio 4, 17 February 2002. https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p009482g. Accessed 19 August 2019.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1996 [1784]. An answer to the question: What is Enlightenment? In Practical philosophy, ed. and trans. Mary M. Gregor, 11–22. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kekes, John. 1993. The morality of pluralism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, Lawrence L. 1982. Versions of survival: The Holocaust and the human spirit. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 1996. The morals of modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Jacob. 2007. It usually begins with Isaiah Berlin. The Good Society 15: 23–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magee, Bryan. 1982. Talking philosophy: Dialogues with fifteen leading philosophers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medina, Marc. 2008. Everyday courage: Living courageously without being a hero. Existential Analysis 19: 280–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mrovlje, Maša. 2019. Rethinking political judgement: Arendt and existentialism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Jan-Werner. 2012. Value pluralism in twentieth-century Anglo-American thought. In Modern pluralism: Anglo-American debates since 1880, ed. Mark Bevir, 81–104. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parekh, Bhikhu. 1996. Moral philosophy and its anti-pluralist bias. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 40: 117–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1996. Political liberalism, expanded edn. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. A defense of abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1: 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trunk, Isaiah. 1996. Judenrat: The Jewish councils in eastern Europe under Nazi occupation. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Allyn Fives and other participants in the ‘Political Obligation and Moral Conflict’ panel at the 2018 MANCEPT Workshops in Political Theory, where I presented an earlier version of this essay. Thanks are also due to Shin Osawa for his feedback; and to Raffaele Rodogno and other members of the Research Unit for Ethics, Legal, and Political Philosophy at Aarhus University for their comments on the penultimate version.

Funding

This article has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie Grant Agreement No. 754513 and the Aarhus University Research Foundation. It has also benefitted from a EURIAS fellowship at the Paris Institute for Advanced Study (France), co-funded by Marie Skłodowska-Curie Actions, under the European Union’s 7th Framework Programme for research, and from a funding from the French State programme ‘Investissements d’avenir’, managed by the Agence Nationale de la Recherche (ANR-11-LABX-0027-01 Labex RFIEA+).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kei Hiruta.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hiruta, K. Value Pluralism, Realism and Pessimism. Res Publica 26, 523–540 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-020-09463-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-020-09463-3

Keywords

Navigation