Skip to main content
Log in

Constitutivism and cognitivism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Constitutivism holds that an account of what a thing is yields those normative standards to which that thing is by nature subject. We articulate a minimal form of constitutivism that we call formal, non-epistemological constitutivism which diverges from orthodox versions of constitutivism in two main respects. First: whereas orthodox versions of constitutivism hold that those ethical norms to which people are by nature subject are sui generis because of their special capacity to motivate action and legitimate criticism, we argue that these features are compatible with treating these norms as of a piece with those ‘formal’ natural-historical norms which can be used to assess living things. Second: unlike orthodox versions of constitutivism, our version does not seek to use a non-normative account of that kind of being which we are as a means of identifying those normative claims to which we are are by nature subject. We then indicate how our position can afford us the resources to address some of the familiar difficulties that face cognitivism in ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We here follow van Roojen (2018) in taking cognitivism to be characterized by the claims that “moral sentences are apt for truth or falsity, and that the state of mind of accepting a moral judgment is typically one of belief” (van Roojen 2018, §1.2). There is significant difficulty in precisely characterizing the distinction between cognitivism and more sophisticated forms of non-cognitivism (see Schroeder 2010, 12–13 and van Roojen 2018, §1.1 for the difficulties of characterizing non-cognitivism). Our aim is to make available a form of cognitivism that does not need to rely on deflationary or other minimal theories of truth (so our account will allow for the truth conditions of moral sentences to be ‘robust’) and does not account for the motivational power of the states of mind characteristically corresponding to normative statements by claiming that those mental states are anything other than beliefs (or even knowledge).

  2. For these questions as the main motivations for non-cognitivism, see Schroeder (2010, ch. 1).

  3. Constitutivism “promises to reveal not merely which norms have genuine authority, but also what their authority consists in” (Silverstein 2016, 215).

  4. Constitutivists must also address a metaphysical question: are the relevant normative claims grounded in our status as agents, and if so, how should agency be understood? Or perhaps they are grounded in our status as human beings? Or is there some other choice available? As we explain in Sect. 2 below, we remain neutral in this paper about the correct answer to this metaphysical question.

  5. We do not take our version of constitutivism to be entirely novel. Kindred views are defended by Lavin (2017) and Fix (2021). For more on their views, see Sect. 2 below. Thanks to an anonymous referee for urging us to pay more attention to these papers.

  6. A terminological point: as we will see in more detail in Sect. 3.1 below, some constitutivists will deny that the normative claims that interest ethicists are specific instances of a genus of normative claims (more generally, claims that express standards of evaluation) that can also be specified to include normative claims about knives. Such constitutivists will hold that only ethical normative claims express ‘true’ normativity, while claims about how knives ought to be are not really normative (see, for example, Silverstein 2016, 225 for a forthright expression of this view). Accordingly, such constitutivists will be reluctant to follow us in calling (4) ‘normative’. We disagree. As we will argue in Sect. 3, according to our formal constitutivist, there is no special form of ‘true’ or ‘robust’ normativity in the case of ethics.

  7. These come in different varieties: Korsgaard (2009) offers a neo-Kantian account, Smith (2013) a Humean account, and Katsafanas (2011, 2013) a Nietzschean account. Velleman (2000, 2009) relies on the idea of self-understanding.

  8. This task is related to the shmagency objection (Enoch, 2006): for any particular account of agency a constitutivist might adopt, she will need to show why that notion of agency is the one which matters for the kind of beings that we all are.

  9. The possibility of a neo-Aristotelian constitutivism is acknowledged in, for example, Silverstein (2016), Haase and Mayr (2019), and Moosavi (2020). Lavin (2017) explicitly pursues an Aristotelian constitutivism. Foot (2001) and Thompson (2008) can also be read as neo-Aristotelian constitutivists.

  10. That is, the authority of (1) puts us in a position to criticize and condemn (Silverstein says that constitutivists aim to “ground authoritative criticisms. They hope to earn the authority to condemn certain agents for acting wrongly or irrationally” (2016, 227)).

  11. Some care is necessary here: if one ought not be X-ing, it may or may not be true that one ought to follow the rules of X-ing when one is X-ing. We set this complication aside here since nothing we say turns on the point.

  12. The presentation in this paragraph is indebted to Ferrero (2019).

  13. The challenge we are describing in this Section is most clearly presented by Silverstein (2016) and Ferrero (2019).

  14. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this label.

  15. Thompson presents this account in his (1995, 2004, 2008).

  16. Recall that what this term picks out varies depending on the answer to the metaphysical question which any specific version of constitutivism will have selected, so that we have a norm to which the Duke is by nature subject. If it is not true that the Duke belongs to this metaphysical category (for example, if some criticism applies simply in virtue of the Duke’s standing as a gentleman) then the norm will not have the kind of legitimacy which is at stake here.

  17. We here follow Thompson (2008, 60) and Foot (2001, 12–13).

  18. This slogan of Thompson’s sounds much like Silverstein’s claim that “reasons for action just are considerations that bear on practical reasoning” (Silverstein 2016, 235). For Silverstein, this embodies a reductive meta-normative theory. That is to say, those considerations to which we attribute robust normativity just are those considerations which have to do with the ‘formal’ aim of practical reasoning. We can accept this identification, but we resist the idea that such an identification accomplishes the goal of reducing the ‘genuinely’ normative to the non-normative. As we’ll argue in Sect. 4 below, in accepting such an identity we accord no justificatory or epistemological priority to practical reasoning over practical reasons. Furthermore, as we’ve argued in this Section, we reject the idea that reasons possess a kind of ‘robust’ normativity which ‘formal’ statements about the aim of practical reasoning lack.

  19. Thanks to two anonymous referees for urging us to clarify our position here.

  20. We take this line of thought to be similar to that propounded in Foot (2001, ch. 4). But Foot’s argument is difficult, and we lay no claim to be faithful exegetes.

  21. These points are emphasized in, for example, Thompson (2008).

  22. Our claims in the last few paragraphs are similar to those made by Fix (2021, 19).

  23. For an overview of some of the semantic theories which have been proposed, see Sterken (2017).

References

  • Enoch, D. (2006). Agency, shmagency: Why normativity won’t come from what is constitutive of action. The Philosophical Review, 115, 169–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero, L. (2019). The simple constitutivist move. Philosophical Explorations, 22(2), 146–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fix, J. D. (2021). Two sorts of constitutivism. Analytic Philosophy, 62(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haase, M., & Mayr, E. (2019). Varieties of constitutivism. Philosophical Explorations, 22(2), 95–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas, P. (2011). Deriving ethics from action: A Nirtzschean version of constitutivism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83, 620–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas, P. (2013). Agency and the foundations of ethics. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas, P. (2018). Constitutivism about practical reasons. In D. Star (Ed.), Oxford handbook of reasons and normativity (pp. 367–393). Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lavin, D. (2017). Forms of rational agency. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 80, 171–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moosavi, P. (2022). Natural goodness without natural history. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 104, 78–100.

  • Schroeder, M. (2010). Noncognitivism in ethics. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2007). Reasons without rationalism. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverstein, M. (2016). Teleology and normativity. In R. Shafer-Laudau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics: 11. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2013). A constitutivist theory of reasons. Law, Ethics, and Philosophy, 1, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterken, R. K. (2017). The meaning of generics. Philosophy Compass, 12, e12431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (1995). The representation of life. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2004). Apprehending human form. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trollope, A. (2011). The Duke’s children. Oxford World’s Classics.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Roojen, M. (2018). Moral cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

  • Velleman, J. D. (2000). The possibility of practical reason. Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2009). How we get along. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to two anonymous referees for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Lockhart.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lockhart, J.R., Lockhart, T. Constitutivism and cognitivism. Philos Stud 179, 3705–3727 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01866-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01866-7

Keywords

Navigation