Skip to main content
Log in

Normative principles and the nature of mind-dependence

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the most fundamental debates in metaethics is whether (subsets of) the normative facts are mind-dependent. Yet some philosophers are skeptical that mind-dependence is a category that's significant in the way metaethicists have assumed it is. In this paper, I consider a puzzle that showcases this skepticism, explaining how it undermines the most natural reading of the mind-dependence claim. I then go on to show that no modification of this reading within a certain class can hope to solve the problem. I conclude by suggesting a new way that mind-dependence should be understood: mind-dependence is ultimately a matter of how normative principles are grounded. I develop this view briefly before concluding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Plato, Euthyphro.

  2. Street (2006: sec. 10), Street (2009: 274). Street says that the reason facts “are a function of” one’s evaluative attitudes. In other places, however, she says that normative truth consists in being entailed from within the practical point of view—Street (2010: 369).

  3. Schroeder (2007).

  4. Shafer-Landau (2003: 8).

  5. McGrath (2010).

  6. Enoch (2011: 3).

  7. See, e.g., Sayre-McCord (1988), Cuneo (2007: 45), Rosati (2017), and Dunaway (2017).

  8. Rosen (1994), Rosati (2017), Dunaway (2017), Shafer-Landau (2003: 15). Enoch (2011: 3–4), Brink (1989: 15).

  9. See, e.g., Enoch (2011: 4), Dunaway (2017: 138), Berker (2014), Clarke-Doane (2012), Schafer (2014), Street (2006: 110–111).

  10. See Brink (1989: 15), Rosen (1994: 287–288), Rosati (2017: 359).

  11. For different kinds of grounding, see Fine (2012).

  12. I.e., I speak in “unionist,” not “separatist” language. See Berker (2019).

  13. Rosati (2017: 359).

  14. Street (2006, 2010) and Schafer (2014).

  15. Shafer-Landau (2003: 15).

  16. It’s possible that K will include some of the relevant happiness facts and not others. This seems unlikely, but even if we could gerrymander such a kind, it would still come out that utilitarians are clearly committed to certain moral facts are mind-dependent, but not others. And we want even these questions left genuinely open, for someone committing only to utilitarianism.

  17. Most famously, Williams (1981), though see Finlay (2009) for a different reading of Williams. See also Johnson (1999). For a related argument in favor of internalist theories of well-being, see Railton (1986) and Rosati (1996).

  18. Schroeder (2007: 1–2).

  19. Railton (1986).

  20. In what follows, I omit the “asymmetrically” qualifier for ease of exposition.

  21. Morton (2020), Rosen (2017a), Bader (2017), Maguire (2015: 194), Berker (2019). See also Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (2014: 401–403), though the authors speak in terms of truth-making, not grounding.

  22. Leary (2017, 2020).

  23. This assumes transitivity of partial grounding. Again, see Fine (2012), and for a critical view, Schaffer (2012). Litland (2013) defends transitivity from objections.

  24. Rosen (2017a: 163), Murphy (2011: 49).

  25. Berker (2019). See also Fogal and Risberg (2020): though they draw the same distinction, they describe it as principles being “explanatory in content” as opposed to “explanatory in role.”

  26. Berker (2018) and (2019).

  27. Versions of the following argument have been made by Morton (2020), Rosen (2017b), and Fogal and Risberg (2020).

  28. Again, see Fine (2012), though (again) irreflexivity is broadly assumed. Wilson (2014) and Correia (2014) are critical of it.

  29. Berker (2019) gives such a view, though not the formulation that follows. Fogal and Risberg (2020) criticize Berker here.

  30. A note about this formulation: it’s not \(\forall\) x(Mx → Mx grounds Gx), in order to allow that the grounds do not entail the grounded. It’s not \(\forall\) x((Gx) → Mx grounds Gx), in order to preserve multiple realizability of the grounded.

  31. Armstrong (1983: ch. 6). See also Murphy (2011) and Rosen (2017b).

  32. Bennett (2011) and deRosset (2013) claim that [A grounds B] is grounded in A; Rosen (2010) and Dasgupta (2014) present a more complex view, which I don’t consider for reasons of space, but which ultimately gets Completeness Matters in the same problem.

  33. Berker (2019) also argues against the view that principles are amongst the grounds of particular normative facts. His argument is similar to mine in some respects, but note that while Berker is arguing that “Principles as Partial Grounds,” as he calls it, entails redundant grounding—something he argues is implausible—I’m arguing that it leaves no room for mind-independence. My argument is in fact compatible with there being redundant grounding in this case. We do, however, both rely on the claim that normative principles are not self-referential in the way Principles as Partial Grounds would require.

  34. This style of argument—account X of distinction P versus not-P is not a good one, since it makes P (or non-P) impossible on broad metaphysical grounds—is not uncommon. Leary (2020) employs this kind of argument against a certain understanding of the naturalism vs. non-naturalism debate.

  35. Berker (2019) endorses (2).

  36. Even “contributory” principles—think Rossian “prima facie duties”—aim to give full grounds for normative phenomena: Ross (2002) is best read as claiming that the fact that Φing would be maleficent (e.g.) is the full explanation of a reason not to Φ.

  37. For a different but related problem, see Berker (2018).

  38. Leary (2020).

  39. Some normative principles, after all, relate the normative to the normative: e.g., “We ought to maximize the good.”

  40. Berker (2019: sec. 4).

  41. Remember that I’m—plausibly, I think—assuming the grounding in each case is full. (I’m also assuming that full grounding is not redundant here, on which point see Berker (2019).

  42. Fine (2012).

  43. Not that there aren’t good arguments: we could modify one of Stephanie Leary’s arguments to work against it (Leary 2020). Leary argues that understanding the naturalism/non-naturalism in terms of whether normative facts are fully grounded in natural ones leads to a misinterpretation of Moore. Moore, after all, seems committed to both non-naturalism and the full grounding of the moral in the natural. Leary argues that we could reinterpret Moore’s claims to just be about normative grounding, but that this would be “a stretch.” Similarly, understanding mind-independence as the denial of metaphysical grounding in the mental would require the same revisionary interpretation of Moore (a textbook mind-independence theorist).

  44. For discussion of such Humean views about normative principles, see Berker (2019) and Fogal and Risberg (2020).

  45. See Fine (2012).

  46. Perhaps, one might think, the non-normative component in the grounds of the particular normative fact will be mental—in which case, the full grounds will be mental. But this will not always be the case: e.g., if well-being is (partially) objective, partially constituted by (say) physical health, and promotion of well-being contributes to an act’s goodness, the grounds of an act’s goodness will include a non-normative, non-mental component.

  47. See Schaffer (2017a) and (2017b).

  48. See Carroll (1895).

  49. Bader (2017: 108n).

  50. Bader (2017: 118).

  51. Glazier (2016) defends principles-as-governors about metaphysical laws (though in terms of explanation, not grounding). Fogal and Risberg (2020) reference principles-as-governors without endorsing it, while Berker (2019) argues against it.

  52. There are tricky questions about counterfactuals here: were A not to endorse the principle of utility, would A endorse a different principle that would result in this act of adultery being wrong? I won’t try to settle that question here. It doesn’t matter: even if the answer is "yes,” the wrongness would still be covarying with the endorsement of some principle that entails the wrongness of acts like that.

  53. Berker (2019: Sect. 8).

  54. Thanks to Gideon Rosen for bring this objection to my attention.

  55. Modulo the assumptions in fn. 41.

  56. For what it’s worth, Type of Grounding Matters offers us a way of keeping the face-value reading of the Euthyphro case while still allowing for mind-dependence. Briefly, the mind-dependence theorist can claim that while piety facts are normatively grounded in facts about respecting one’s parents, they are metaphysically grounded in the gods’ lovings.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bader, R. (2017). The grounding argument against non-reductive moral realism. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 12, pp. 106–134). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011). By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 27–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2014). Does evolutionary psychology show that normativity is mind-dependent? In D. Jacobson, & J. D'Arms(Eds.), Moral psychology and human agency: Philosophical essays on the science of ethics (pp. 215–252). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2018). The unity of grounding. Mind, 127, 729–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2019). The explanatory ambitions of moral principles. Nous, 53, 904–936.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1985). What the tortoise said to achilles. Mind, 4, 278–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke-Doane, J. (2012). Morality and mathematics: The evolutionary challenge. Ethics, 122, 313–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2014). Logical grounds. Review of Symbolic Logic, 7, 31–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2007). The normative web: An argument for moral realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T., & Shafer-Landau, R. (2014). The moral fixed points: New directions for moral nonnaturalism. Philosophical Studies, 171, 399–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). The possibility of physicalism. Journal of Philosophy, 111, 557–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • deRosset, L. (2013). Grounding explanations. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunaway, B. (2017). Realism and objectivity. In T. McPherson & D. Plunkett (Eds.), The routledge handbook of metaethics (pp. 135–150). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schneider (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, S. (2009). The obscurity of internal reasons. Philosophers’ Imprint, 9, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogal, D., & Risberg, O. (2020). The metaphysics of moral explanations. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 15, pp. 170–194). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Glazier, M. (2016). Laws and the completeness of the fundamental. In M. Jago (Ed.), Reality making (pp. 11–37). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. (1999). Internal reasons and the conditional fallacy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 53–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2015). Moral anti-realism. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-anti-realism/.

  • Leary, S. (2017). Non-naturalism and normative necessities. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 12, pp. 76–105). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leary, S. (2020). Normativity. In M. Raven (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of metaphysical grounding (pp. 472–483). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Litland, J. E. (2013). On some counterexamples to the transitivity of grounding. Essays in Philosophy, 14, 19–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maguire, B. (2015). Grounding the autonomy of ethics. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 10, pp. 188–215). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. (2010). Moral realism without convergence. Philosophical Topics, 38, 59–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, J. (2020). Grounding the normative: A problem for structured non-naturalism. Philosophical Studies, 177, 173–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. (2011). God and moral law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997). Euthyphro. Trans. G.M.A. Grube. In J. Cooper, (Ed.), Plato: Complete works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Railton, P. (1986). Facts and values. Philosophical Topics, 14, 5–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. (1996). Internalism and the good for a person. Ethics, 106, 297–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. (2017). Mind-dependence and moral realism. In T. McPherson & D. Plunkett (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of metaethics (pp. 355–370). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (1994). Objectivity and modern idealism: What is the question? In M. Michael & J. O. Leary-Hawthorne (Eds.), Philosophy in mind (pp. 277–319). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality, metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2017). What is a moral law? In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 12, pp. 135–159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2017a). Metaphysical relations in metaethics. In T. McPherson & D. Plunkett (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of metaethics (pp. 151–169). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (2002). The right and the good. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sayre-McCord, G. (1988). Introduction: The many moral realisms. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 1–23). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schafer, K. (2014). Constructivism and three forms of perspective-dependence in metaethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89, 68–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2012). Grounding, transitivity, and contrastivity. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding (pp. 122–138). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2017a). The ground between the gaps. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2017b). Laws for metaphysical explanation. Philosophical Issues, 27, 302–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2009). In defense of future tuesday indifference: Ideally coherent eccentrics and the contingency of what matters. Philosophical Issues, 19, 273–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2010). What is constructivism in ethics and metaethics? Philosophy Compass, 5, 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Internal and external reasons. In B. Williams (Ed.), His moral luck (pp. 101–113). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2014). No work for a theory of grounding. Inquiry, 57, 535–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin Morton.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Morton, J. Normative principles and the nature of mind-dependence. Philos Stud 179, 1153–1176 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01692-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01692-3

Keywords

Navigation