1 Introduction

Here are two questions:

  • What is the meaning of the word ‘believe’?

  • What is belief?

The former question tends to occupy semanticists while the latter is the focus of philosophical discussions in epistemology and philosophy of mind.

On the surface of it, the questions seem related. We might expect a theory of the meaning of ‘believe’ to tell us what it takes for a sentence of the form ‘x believes that p’ to be true. To have this knowledge would seem to help us understand what belief is. However, in practice when semanticists answer questions about the meaning of a term like ‘believe’ they tend to rely on cognate terms in their metalanguage. Philosophers interested in belief are not going be content with being told that for x to believe p is for x to bear the belief-relation to the proposition p.

However, I think considerations from the semantics of ‘believe’ have a non-trivial bearing on how philosophers ought to think about belief. My discussion will mostly center on the claim that belief attributions are in a certain sense weak made in ‘Belief is weak’ (Hawthorne, Rothschild, and Spector 2016, henceforth HRS). I’ll first elaborate and defend that claim, responding in detail to an interesting challenge from recent work on homogeneity in natural language. I will move on to discussing the potential implications of the weakness of belief for philosophical accounts of belief. I will argue that while the semantic considerations might naturally support the Lockean view of belief, they can also be leveraged to support other positions.Footnote 1

2 Three claims about the weakness of belief

Here are the key claims from HRS I want to revisit:

  1. (A)

    The attitude verbs ‘believe’ and ‘think’ semantically express the same attitude.Footnote 2

  2. (B)

    ‘Believe’/‘think’ have a semantically weak reading on which ‘Lilly believes/thinks p’ is true even when Lilly thinks that p is only likely.

  3. (C)

    ‘Believe’/‘think’ never have a very strong lexical meanings, i.e., in no context does ‘Lily thinks p’ come to mean Lily has ruled out the possibility of not p or is sure/certain that p.

Before going on to the evidence for these claims I want to clarify them in three respects: first, I will say a bit more about what I mean by weakness in (B); second, I will discuss the relationship between these claims and philosophical orthodoxy about ‘belief’; and, third, I will discuss the relationship between these claims and the pragmatics of belief-ascriptions.

In HRS, ‘we argue[d] that believing a proposition merely requires thinking it likely’. I still hold that view, but it requires more clarification. I do not take the view that ‘believing that p is likely’ is equivalent to ‘believing that p’. Rather I hold that insofar as there are probabilistic or evidential requirements on believing that p they do not go beyond the probabilistic or evidential requirements on believing that p is likely. This does not preclude there being other, non-probabilistic requirements on belief.Footnote 3 (B) simply states that ‘believe’ can be weak in this sense; (C) says it never has a reading with the stronger commitment that believing p requires being certain that p.

Williamson (2018) argues that the view of the meaning of ‘believe’, above, particularly, (C), is implausible as it requires thinking that generations of epistemologists have simply been confused about the words they have used.

...if believing p likely suffices for believing p, an obvious question arises as to whether someone who accepts p only as far as thinking p likely can count as knowing p, however well they do on the other conditions. Yet when the most detailed survey of post-Gettier epistemology considers published worries about the belief condition, including several motivated by concerns about ordinary usage, they are all to the effect that it is too strong, not that it is too weak (Shope 1983: 171–192). In a published literature to which hundreds of native speakers of English contributed, quite a few of them ordinary language philosophers alert to nuances of natural language, it would be odd that people did not object to what would arguably be a gross misuse of ‘believe’, if HRS were right.

I am not arguing that stereotypical instances of belief attributions do not, in fact, involve strong belief, i.e., being sure or certain, or that we cannot in certain contexts use sentences like ‘John believes p’ to convey the thought (somehow or other) that John is sure that p. All I am arguing is that the verb ‘believe’ does not have such a strong reading.

To give an analogy, I take it that ‘open the car door’ means, roughly speaking, to move the car door in such a way as to allow ingress into the car. However, generally when we talk about people opening the car door, we mean that they do so in the normal manner: using the handle, rather than, say, a chainsaw or a crowbar. But I wouldn’t want to say that the expression ‘open the car door’ ever actually means to open the car door in the usual way. Rather, in many cases it is simply a tacit conversational assumption that if someone opened a car door they did so in the normal way. Similarly while talk of belief often attributes, in some sense, certainty, I think this is not part of the contextual meaning of the attitude verb ‘believe’.Footnote 4 If we convey stronger meanings using ‘believe’ and ‘think’, it is only by post-compositional pragmatic inference.Footnote 5

In the next section I’ll go through the most powerful arguments in HRS for these claims.

3 The arguments

  • Let’s start with (A).Footnote 6 If ‘believe’ and ‘think’ express extensionally different attitudes then it should be possible to at once to assert one and deny the other. It is not possible, however, as (1) demonstrates.Footnote 7

    1. (1)

      ?Even if she thinks John is at the party, it’s not fair to say she believes it.

    Compare:

    1. (2)

      Even if she thinks John is at the party, it’s not fair to say she’s certain of it.

    Similarly, we cannot contrast the two attitudes with ‘but’.

    1. (3)

      ? Bill thinks John is at the party, but Heather believes he is.

    Compare:Footnote 8

    1. (4)

      Bill thinks John is at the party, but Heather is sure he is.

  • Now let us move on to the arguments for (B). First, observe that ‘believe’ is neg-raising. That is, the following two sentences can be read as equivalent:

    1. (5)
      1. a.

        I don’t believe Jesus wept.

      2. b.

        I believe Jesus didn’t weep.

    As Horn (1978, 1989) observes, neg-raising verbs tend to be weak. He writes:

    What is common to all NR predicates is the relative slimness of the functional difference between the preraised form with lower negation and the logical form with the upstairs negative taking wide scope. It is the closeness of the external (contradictory) readings of not likely, not believe, not advisable to, likely not, believe not, advisable not, respectively, which renders the negated predicates potential neg-raisers, and the relative distance of not possible, not realize, not obligatory from possible not, realize not, obligatory not which removes these from contention. (Horn 1978, p. 196)

    The point is that if ‘believe’ is strong, then its negation is not going to be close to not believing. But if ‘believe’ has a weak reading (close to believing likely) than we get the slim functional difference Horn describes as characterizing the class of neg-raisers generally.

    It is worth noting that this not just a useful generalization about neg-raisers but also provides a clue to understanding why there is neg-raising to begin with. For instance, if ‘likely p’ just means ‘p is more likely than not,’ to infer ‘likely not p’ from ‘not likely p’ all we have to assume is that p and not p don’t have exactly the same likelihood. If the speaker can be taken to be making this assumption, then an assertion of ‘not likely p’ will come to mean ‘likely not p’. Thus the slim functional difference Horn describes fits in well with the view that neg-raising is a kind of conversational implicature. However, there is no consensus in the literature that neg-raising is the result of an implicature.Footnote 9

    Another piece of evidence for the weakness of belief is the presuppositional behavior of ‘believe’ under questions:

    1. (6)

      Who does Tom think/believe won the election?

      \(\not \leadsto\) There is someone Tom is sure won the election.

    Normally a question presupposes that there is one true answer. Compare:

    1. (7)

      Who is Tom sure won the election?

      \(\leadsto\) There is someone Tom is sure won the election.

    The natural explanation of why (6) carries a weak presupposition (or none at all) is simply that ‘think’/‘believe’ is weaker than ‘be sure’. If it simply means ‘think likely’ then (6) would presuppose only that Tom thought one candidate more likely to have won than another, which is surely the most it could be felt to presuppose.

    Another argument for a weak reading of ‘believe’ is the coherence of the following sentence:

    1. (8)

      William thinks/believes it’s raining, but he’s not sure.

    If ‘believe’/‘think’ only had a strong reading this would not be coherent. Direct evidence for the idea that believing p means thinking p likely comes from cases of prediction. An assertion of:

    1. (9)

      Lily thinks/believes Jose won the race.

    seems to require only that Lily thinks Jose is the most likely winner, not that she is sure Jose won.Footnote 10 As HRS point out, this type of statement can be used to ascribe belief in cases where the believed probability of the proposition is less than .5 (though greater than all the relevant alternatives). This suggests that meaning of ‘believe’ or ‘think’ is really much weaker than that of ‘be sure’.

  • I will now turn to evidence for the stronger claim (C), that ‘think’ and believe’ lack strong readings. The way I argue for this claim, as in HRS, is to show that even in circumstances in which a strong reading of ‘think’ or ‘believe’ would be necessary for a sentence to be coherent, that reading is still not available. (10) is an example of this type.

    1. (10)

      ? It’s not that Tim thinks John will win, nor that he doesn’t think John won’t win, but he thinks it is likely John will win.

    If we read ‘think’ as strong (10) should make perfect sense, but it doesn’t.Footnote 11

    A related example is:

    1. (11)

      ? While I SUSPECT Tim is at the party, it’s not that I THINK/BELIEVE he is.

    For a control, contrast this with:

    1. (12)

      While I SUSPECT Tim is at the party, it’s not that I am SURE he is.

    Another contrast:

    1. (13)
      1. a.

        ? Lilly only SUSPECTS that Bill stole the painting, but Bill THINKS/BELIEVES he did.

      2. b.

        Lilly only SUSPECTS that Bill stole the painting, but Bill is SURE he did.

    If ‘thinks/believes’ had a possible reading in which they attribute certainty we would expect that reading to be accessed in (13-a). But the infelicity of (13-a) suggests we cannot access this stronger reading.Footnote 12

    Here is another example that suggests that ‘to believe p’ can never mean to be sure that p (this comes from Levi Spectre, p.c.):

    1. (14)

      A: Can you pay for this?

      B: Sorry, but I don’t have any money left in my account.

      A: \(\checkmark\) Are you sure/certain you don’t ?

      ? Do you believe/think you don’t?

    What is odd here is that the variant of A’s answer using ‘believe’ or ‘think’ is infelicitous. If ‘believe’ really did have a strong reading one would expect that reading to be accessed in this context and the contribution to be felicitous.

Before closing this section, I should comment on the relative strength of the different linguistic evidence. I consider the evidence for (A) to be strong: ‘believe’ does not systematically have a higher evidential requirement than ‘think’. If anything, the reverse is true: ‘believe’ seems to have a use that suggests belief despite knowing the odds are against you.Footnote 13 I consider the evidence for (B) to be definitive: it is completely clear that ‘believe’ and ‘think’ have easily available weak readings. The case for (C) is more tenative. There is suggestive evidence that strong readings are not available. This evidence might best be considered as a challenge to those who think that the strong readings should be the most easily accessible and prominent ones, rather than as constituting a solid case against the existence of those readings.

4 Homogeneous, strong belief

Despite these arguments, there is a rival view that can be teased out of the recent semantics literature that ‘believe’ is strong. Križ (2015) gives a general theory of homogeneity (the way certain terms require all-or-nothing readings) and applies it to attitude verbs such as ‘believe’.Footnote 14 In this section I will present a version of his homogeneous semantics for attitude verbs that seems to make ‘believe’ strong in an empirically plausible way.

Let me first outline the essential features of this homogeneous view of belief. We begin with a strong, Hintikkian semantics of ‘believe’: for x to believe p is for every world doxastically accessible to x to be a p-world.Footnote 15 However, we classify ‘believe’ as a homogeneous expression in the sense developed by Križ. We then appeal to special properties of homogeneous expressions to reply to the arguments of HRS.

I should note that is not clear to me that this view is Križ’s. For Križ does not discuss what maximal readings of belief amount to, i.e. whether believing p is tantamount to being sure that p, or ruling out all doxastic possibilities that not-p in the usual sense. The only commitment of the homogeneity-view is that ‘believe’ acts as a universal quantifier over belief-worlds (however exactly belief-worlds are understood). The strength of such a universal semantics for ‘believe’ will depend on what the worlds quantifying over are: if these are a subset of the worlds that are doxastically possible in the normal sense then the view might be weak. Thus, we need to add to Križ’s view the commitment to ‘believe’ being strong. This commitment yields a position that is similar to the position by Moss (forthcoming). Moss argues that believing p is tantamount to being certain that p, and that loose talk accounts for the way in which we often ascribe belief in cases that fall short of certainty.Footnote 16 Križ (ch. 3) also uses the the idea of loose talk in his treatment of homogeneity, arguing that the non-maximal reading (explained below) should be accounted for in terms of it. So both views share a strong basic semantics and a pragmatic weakening mechanism involving loose talk.Footnote 17

In the rest of this section, I’ll outline some of the main characteristics of homogeneous expressions, and explain why we might think that ‘believe’ satisfies them. The four features I will focus on are strength, strong negation, non-maximality, and non-presupposition. Expressions that exhibit these properties, according to Križ, include plural definites, conditionals, questions, and bare plurals as well as neg-raising attitude verbs such as ‘believe’. I’ll use plural definites to illustrate these properties, as they are the canonical example of a homogeneous expression-type and the focus of much of Križ’s work.

Let’s go through the four properties.

  1. I.

    strength: an unembedded assertion of a plural definite entails (at least as a default) something like a universal reading:

    1. (15)

      The boys passed.

      \(\leadsto\) All the boys passed.

    Similarly the strong theorist of belief thinks that normal belief attributions have strong entailments: e.g. ‘believes p’ entails ‘is sure that p’.

  2. II.

    Combined with strength we also have strong negation: under negation a plural definite acts as if it is weak, leading to a stronger reading than expected:

    1. (16)

      I doubt the boys passed.

      \(\leadsto\) I think none of the boys passed.

    This contrasts with:

    1. (17)

      I doubt all the boys passed.

    Another way of seeing this phenomenon is to note that negation acts as though it is scopeless with respect to ‘the boys’, but negation has a scope ambiguity with respect to ‘all the boys’.

    1. (18)
      1. a.

        The boys don’t like me.

      2. b.

        All the boys don’t like me.

    The neg-raising property of ‘believe’ can now be explained as being the result of strong negation.

    1. (19)

      John doesn’t believe it’s raining

      \(\leadsto\) John believes it isn’t raining.

    This explanation of neg-raising is surprising since HRS used neg-raising as an argument for a semantics for weak belief. We pointed out that in general neg-raising verbs are weaker; for example, ‘love’ is not neg-raising but ‘like’ is. However, in the context of Gajewski and Križ’s observations this argument for belief being weak clearly does not work.Footnote 18

  3. III.

    non-maximality is the property that plural definites can tolerate some exceptions to their universality:Footnote 19

    1. (20)

      The boys came although little Sam stayed at home as he was ill.

    versus

    1. (21)

      ? All the boys came although little Sam stayed at home as he was ill.

    As we shall see in the next section non-maximality is one of the most subtle properties of homogeneous expressions. While we tolerate exceptions, we cannot straightforwardly list counterexamples to the universal claims of plural definites:

    1. (22)

      ? Athena stayed on Mount Olympus but the children of Zeus went down to Hades.

    Similarly non-maximality leads to an explanation of why we can have weak readings of ‘believe’ but not ‘sure’, as shown in this contrast:

    1. (23)
      1. a.

        John believes it’s raining, but he has doubts.

      2. b.

        ? John is sure it’s raining, but he has doubts.

    Note that we can make an explicit analogy here: ‘the boys’ : ‘all the boys’ as ‘thinking that’ : ‘being certain/sure that’. In each case, the two expressions have similar meanings but only the expression to the left of the colon is homogeneous.

  4. IV.

    Generally when an expression and its negation both lead to an entailment we say that the entailment is presupposed.Footnote 20 There is a common content to both (24) and (25):

    1. (24)

      The boys passed.

    2. (25)

      The boys didn’t pass.

    The common content is that all the boys passed or all the boys didn’t. However, this content does not behave like a presupposition.

    1. (26)

      If the boys passed, then I’ll be happy.

      \(\not \leadsto\) Either the boys all passed or they all didn’t pass.

    Compare to how the presupposition of ‘stop’ behaves in the antecedent of a conditional:

    1. (27)

      If Wisconsin stops electing Republican governors, UW will prosper.

      \(\leadsto\) Wisconsin has been electing Republican governors.

    I call this property of having some common content that does not behave like a presupposition the non-presupposition of homogeneous expressions. Belief attributions clearly share this property, as this example shows:

    1. (28)

      If Lilly thinks it’s raining, she’ll bring her umbrella.

      \(\not \leadsto\) Either Lilly is confident it’s raining or she’s confident it’s not raining.

Thus, there seems to be good evidence that ‘believe’ behaves like a homogeneous expression. To have a strong, homogeneous view of ‘believe’, we might want to adopt the semantics and pragmatics that Križ (2015) uses in his dissertation for all homogeneous expressions. We need not go through the details here, but the basic idea is to use a trivalent semantics that makes ‘x believes p’ true iff all of x’s belief-worlds are ones in which p is true, false iff all of x’s belief-worlds are ones in which p is false, and neither true nor false in other cases.Footnote 21 The trivalent logic naturally explains neg-raising, since the conditions for the negation of a sentence to be true require more than just the sentence failing to be true. Moreover Križ (2015, ch. 3) provides a compelling account of non-maximality as loose speech, which seems to have the potential to explain why, although belief is semantically strong, we can attribute belief in cases where people only have high credences.

5 Against homogeneous, strong belief

I do not think that the strong, homogeneous view of ‘believe’ is correct. I am attracted in general to Križ’s account of homogeneity and its potential to unify an array of diverse and puzzling semantic and pragmatic phenomena. And I am prepared to concede that belief attributions might even be homogeneous. However, I do not think that belief attributions—homogeneous or not—are semantically strong (i.e., that literally believing p requires ruling out the possibility that p is false). I have two arguments against the homogeneous strong belief hypothesis.

  • First, the observed weakness of belief is not adequately explained by non-maximality. Note, first, that with plural definites it is not, in general, possible to assert both the plural definite and a negative witness in one breath.Footnote 22

    1. (29)

      ? The students passed but one of them didn’t.

    By contrast it is possible, as HRS observe, to assert belief while expressing doubts (in one breath):

    1. (30)

      [Context: open question that it’s raining] Tilly thinks it’s raining, but she’s not sure.

    2. (31)

      [Context: common ground that it’s raining] Tilly thinks it’s raining, but she doesn’t know it.

    As I said, there are some cases in which one can explicitly discuss exceptions with plural definites, but these are rather special cases such as the following examples from Križ (2015, p. 72):

    1. (32)
      1. a.

        The professors are smiling. Of course, not Smith, but you know, he never smiles; it doesn’t mean anything.

      2. b.

        The townspeople are asleep. Of course, the gatekeeper is probably still up, but we know that he’s always there anyway.

    non-maximality is fragile and seems to be order-dependent with plural definites. We can contrast (32) with (33).Footnote 23

    1. (33)

      Smith isn’t smiling, but you know, he never smiles; it doesn’t mean anything. Still, the professors are smiling.

    In (33), unlike in (32), one gets a strong contextual inference that Smith is not a professor. No such pattern can be seen with exceptions to belief statements, where either order seems fine.

    1. (34)

      Tilly isn’t sure Steve passed, but she still believes/thinks he passed.

  • The second reason I do not accept the homogeneous view is that belief attributions simply do not behave as if they are as semantically strong as attributions of sureness/certainty. I have already given arguments for this claim in section 3, particularly in the context of examples (11) and (14).

    For more evidence in this vein, specifically distinguishing belief-attributions from plural definites, consider this contrast:Footnote 24

    1. (35)
      1. a.

        ? Bill and Lilly’s children came to the event, in fact, all of them did.

      2. b.

        I believe it’s raining, in fact, I am certain/sure it’s raining.

    The infelicity of (35-a) is evidence that ‘Bill and Lilly’s children’ is almost the same in meaning as ‘All of Bill and Lilly’s children, however, the felicity of (35-b) suggests that ‘I believe p’ does not bear such a close relationship to ‘I am certain/sure that p’.

I conclude that we should not treat ‘believe’ as a strong, homogeneous expression in the sense I explored in the previous section.

6 What it takes

What type of semantics can we give ‘believe’/‘think’ that would explain the kind of behavior I outlined above? What do the semantic considerations above tell us, if anything, about the nature of the mental states we commonly call beliefs? I will go through a few proposals.

6.1 Believing as being sure

Some philosophers want to equate belief with certainty or probability one.Footnote 25 While it may be that certainty plays an essential role in our mental lives, my arguments here suggest that ‘be certain’ is not even a contextually possible meaning of ‘believe’. For this reason, I think it is a mistake to use the English verb ‘believe’ as a philosophical term for the state of being sure or certain.

6.2 Lockeanism

Here is Foley (1992) explicating a classic version of the Lockean thesis:

To say that we believe a proposition is just to say that we are sufficiently confident of its truth for our attitude to be one of belief. Then it is epistemically rational for us to believe a proposition just in case it is epistemically rational for us to have sufficiently high degree of confidence in it, sufficiently high to make our attitude towards it one of belief.

This view equates belief with having sufficient confidence in a proposition. HRS argue that the behavior of the word ‘believe’ would seem to support such a Lockean view as long as the threshold is sufficiently low to account for the data. In particular, while the threshold may exhibit some context sensitivity, some of the cases above show that in many cases we cannot access a reading of ‘believe’ with a high threshold, even where it is strongly favored by context.

There are a number of unresolved problems facing the Lockean view, however, perhaps the most pressing being the failure of closure (Kyburg 1961). It seems, after all, a basic datum of natural language inference that belief is closed under conjunction:Footnote 26

  1. (36)

    ? John believes it will rain today and he believes it will rain tomorrow, but he doesn’t believe it will rain today and tomorrow.

Another worry about the Lockean view comes from considering epistemic contradictions involving belief. Both (37) and (38-b) sound as though they attribute contradictory beliefs to John.Footnote 27

  1. (37)

    ? John thinks [it’s raining but it might not be raining].

  2. (38)
    1. a.

      John thinks/believes it’s raining but he knows/realizes/acknowledges it might not be.

    2. b.

      ? John thinks it’s raining but he thinks it might not be raining.

The Lockean needs to explain why these examples sound contradictory: To believe might not-p seems generally just to require having not-p being compatible with one’s belief.Footnote 28 Then if believing p only requires believing p is likely, it should be possible to both believe p and believe that p might not be true. Luckily Beddor and Goldstein (2017) have already done the work of explaining why (37) is bad despite belief being weak. However, what explains the contrast between (38-a) and (38-b) remains an open question and a pressing one for the Lockean.Footnote 29

6.3 Knowledge first (belief last)

Here is Williamson’s description of his knowledge-first account of belief.

...to believe p is to treat p as if one knew p—that is, to treat p in ways similar to the ways in which subjects treat propositions which they know. In particular, a factive propositional attitude to a proposition is characteristically associated with reliance on it as a premise in practical reasoning, for good functional reasons; such reliance is crucial to belief. A creature which lacks a concept of knowing can still treat a proposition in ways in which it treats propositions which it knows. The primitive creature does not treat the proposition that food is present like that when merely desiring that food is present; it does not use the proposition as a premise in practical reasoning. By contrast, the person who genuinely believes that there is a god by a leap of faith does rely on that premise in such reasoning. The unconfident examinee who tentatively gives p as an answer is little disposed to rely on p as a premise, and for that reason does not clearly believe p, but for the same reason does not clearly know p. Although a full-blown exact conceptual analysis of believes in terms of knows is too much to expect, we can still postulate a looser connection along these lines. (Williamson 2000, pp. 46–47)

One feature of this view which HRS picked out to criticize is Williamson’s claim that knowledge is the ‘norm’ of ‘believe’ (i.e. believe p only if you know that p). We pointed out that this view seemed improbable since it does not suggest any form of error or irrationality to both attribute a belief to an individual and deny that they know it.

  1. (39)

    John doesn’t know Bill is his friend, but he believes he is.

Rather (39) simply seems to say, on one prominent reading, that John lacks the kind of evidence or confidence necessary for knowledge. In this example, then, whatever state we are attributing to John is not one of which knowledge could be the norm of. Thus at least some attributions of belief appear to be attributing a different kind of state from the one Williamson describes.

Williamson (2018) has responded to many of the arguments in HRS, conceding in effect that there is a use of ‘believe p’ in which it expresses a relatively weak form of commitment (presumably rationally compatible with taking oneself not to know p). However, Williamson insists that ‘believe’ can and often does express the stronger ‘full belief’ or ‘outright belief’ of his knowledge-first account. While Williamson does not think full belief in p requires certainty in p in the usual sense, it would seem to be incompatible with taking oneself not to know p. There does not seem to me to be good evidence that ‘believe’ gets to have such a strong reading.

To support his view, Williamson suggests that our locution ‘fully believe’ directly expresses the paradigmatic state of outright belief that comes out of his knowledge-first account. However, consideration of actual usage of ‘fully believe’, I think, tells against this suggestion. Consider (40):Footnote 30

  1. (40)

    Amanda doesn’t know Peter will come home, but she fully believes he will.

As far as I understand it, Williamson takes full belief in p to be a state in which one accepts p to the same extent that one would accept p if one knew p. However, as I read (40) it is attributing to Amanda a belief which self-consciously lacks the normal support enjoyed by knowledge.Footnote 31 Similarly a first person case is no admission of irrationality:

  1. (41)

    I don’t know Peter will come, but I fully believe it.

More generally, I worry that Williamson’s account has too little to say about the semantics of ‘believe’ to give a satisfying explanation of its behavior. For instance, if ‘believing p’ expresses as its primary meaning a commitment to p similar to the commitment we would have if we knew p, it is mysterious why it should be so easy to use ‘believing p’ to express a relatively weak state such as merely thinking p likely. Williamson (2018) argues these weaker states are similar to knowledge states, but he gives no particular account of why ‘believe’ should express the particular range of states that it does.Footnote 32\(^,\)Footnote 33 Thus, even if believing does involve being in knowledge-like states, this connection does little to explain how we talk about belief. The Lockean view, by contrast, directly explains why belief attributions are true of those propositions that we think more likely than not: as on the Lockean view that is just what ‘believe’ means.Footnote 34

7 Hintikkian mysterianism

The Lockean view is often taken to be opposed to the classic view attributed to Hintikka (1962) according to which ‘believe’ can be understood as expressing universal quantification over those worlds compatible with one’s belief. This view has both been dominant in epistemic logic and in natural language semantics. It is natural to oppose Hintikka’s universal quantification view to the Lockean view since the former has it that belief rules out doubt while the latter has it that belief is compatible with considerable doubt.Footnote 35

However, merely taking ‘believe’ to express universal quantification over some worlds does not necessarily make belief strong.Footnote 36 We could have a view, thus, that fails to identify the belief worlds—the worlds quantified over in belief attributions—with doxastic possibilities in the usual sense. Rather the belief worlds would be a subset of the doxastic possibilities, though presumably a subset with a reasonably high probability.

One thing this view could do is provide a satisfying explanation of the contrast in (38) repeated here:

  1. (38)
    1. a.

      John thinks/believes it’s raining but he knows/realizes/acknowledges it might not be.

    2. b.

      ? John thinks it’s raining but he thinks it might not be raining.

The key idea is that ‘might,’ when embedded in this belief report, requires that there be a belief-world in which it doesn’t rain, leading to the contradictory sense of (38-b). Whereas when ‘might’ is embedded under other attitude verbs it does not force there be such belief-worlds (since its force is not derivative on its embedding inside belief).Footnote 37

Of course, such a view would also explain the closure of attitudes under conjunction, since this follows immediately from the universal quantification posited for belief attributions. Moreover, this view is compatible with a homogeneity-type treatment of belief-attributions, and thus a natural explanation of neg-raising.

However, I label this view a mysterian one, as I have little idea how we determine what the belief worlds are if they are not simply those worlds that we consider possible in the usual, epistemic sense.Footnote 38 In so far as we are just interested in semantics, this may be as far as we need to go, however.Footnote 39 It is worth noting, though, that this view is not strictly compatible with Lockeanism: merely having a high enough probability in a proposition is compatible with believing, it but it is not a sufficient condition.Footnote 40

8 Semantics and belief

I hope the data and arguments I’ve presented here have been illustrative of both the power and the limits of the type of thinking we find in natural language semantics. At the least, I hope I’ve shown that those theorists who want to argue for a particularly strong notion of belief, must distance themselves from how we speak about believing. I am, however, not at all certain how philosophers should think about belief.