Skip to main content
Log in

The myth of the myth of supervenience

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Supervenience is necessary co-variation between two sets of entities (properties, facts, objects, etc.). In the good old days, supervenience was considered a useful philosophical tool with a wide range of applications in the philosophy of mind, metaethics, epistemology, and elsewhere. In recent years, however, supervenience has fallen out of favor, giving place to grounding, realization, and other, more metaphysically “meaty”, notions. The emerging consensus is that there are principled reasons for which explanatory theses cannot be captured in terms of supervenience, or as the slogan goes: “Supervenience Is Nonexplanatory” (SIN). While SIN is widely endorsed, it is far from clear what it amounts to and why we should believe it. In this paper, I will distinguish various theses that could be meant by it, and will argue that none of them is both interesting and plausible: on some interpretations of ‘explanatory’, we have no reason to believe that supervenience is unexplanatory, while on other interpretations, supervenience is indeed unexplanatory, but widely accepted textbook cases of explanatory relations come out as unexplanatory, too. This result raises doubts as to whether there is any interesting sense in which SIN is true, and suggests that the contemporary consensus about supervenience is mistaken.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Davidson (1970/1980), Horgan (1982), Lewis (1983), Chalmers (1996), Jackson (1998), and many, many others.

  2. Hare (1952) and Klagge (1988).

  3. Van Cleve (1985), Sosa (1991), and Conee and Feldman (2004).

  4. See Petrie (1987), McLaughlin (1995), and Sider (1999), to just name a few pieces from the vast literature on the various entailment connections between different forms of supervenience.

  5. Horgan (1982) and Hoffman and Newen (2007).

  6. Shagrir (2002) and Bennett (2004).

  7. See DePaul (1987), Horgan (1993), McLaughlin (1995: 18), Shagrir and Hoffman-Kolss (2013), and Endicott (2016: 2207), among others.

  8. See, for example, Fine (2001, 2012), Schaffer (2009: 364), Raven (2012: 690), deRosset (2013: 2), and Trogdon (2013: 101). Even those who attack grounding tend to agree that supervenience has no explanatory value; see Koslicki (2014) and Wilson (2014).

  9. Backing theorists include Ruben (1990), Kim (1994), Audi (2012), Schaffer (2012, 2016), Skiles (2015), and many others. Kim (1994) prefers the name ‘explanatory realism’, which I find misleading (one can be a realist about explanation without thinking of it in terms of underlying relations). Many philosophers use the word ‘grounding’ for a type of explanation, rather than the underlying relation (e.g. Fine 2012; DeRosset 2013; Dasgupta 2014). Raven (2015) refers to such philosophers as “unionists”, and to those who distinguish grounding from metaphysical explanation as “separatists”. I should note that while unionists reject the idea that grounding undergirds metaphysical explanation, they don’t thereby deny that something undergirds it. So, the Backing Model is strictly weaker than separatism. Indeed, even many grounding skeptics, such as Wilson (2014), subscribe to some version of the Backing Model.

  10. See Blackburn (1985) and Horgan and Timmons (1992) for influential statements of this idea, and Zangwill (1997) for an opposing view. See McKenzie (2014: 357) for a recent example of someone who mentions SIN and the “no-bruteness” principle in the same breath.

  11. Indeed, Lewis was an ardent denier of brute necessary connections, yet he often seemed to write as if he thought of supervenience as a broadly explanatory notion; see, e.g., Lewis (1983: 358–359).

  12. Thanks to an anonymous referee, who drew my attention to this related concern.

  13. I borrow this tripartite taxonomy from Trogdon (2017).

  14. Thanks to Jessica Wilson for drawing my attention to this worry.

  15. See Yablo (1992), Horgan (1993), and Wilson (1999), among others.

  16. For instance, deRosset (2010) and Audi (2012) deny that grounding implies “nothing-over-and-above”-ness, and Ridge (2007) is plausibly read as denying that realization does.

  17. See Correia (2008), Koslicki (2013), and Tahko and Lowe (2016) for useful surveys on ontological dependence.

  18. A number of authors have made this point by now: see, for insance, McKenzie (2017), Schnieder (2017), and Kovacs (2018). Grimes (1991) recognized the conceptual distinction between dependence and determination much earlier on, although (as was typical at the time) he tried to capture it with finer-grained notions of supervenience.

  19. For example, Correia (2008) distinguishes between “rigid dependence”, where the dependee requires the existence of some particular dependent thing, and “generic dependence”, where it only requires a certain kind of dependent thing. This is a fairly standard distinction in the ontological dependence literature.

  20. See Correia (2005: 36–37) for a similar point about the relation between supervenience and ontological dependence; cf. Grimes (1991).

  21. See, for instance, Schaffer (2009: 364), McLaughlin and Bennett (2018: §3, §5), and Raven (2012: 690).

  22. Pace Bliss (2014) and Wilson (2014). See Kovacs (2017a) for a general defense of the irreflexivity of explanation and explanatory relations.

  23. Salmon (1977/1997: 95–96) and Audi (2012: 699–701) accept the minimality constraint; Fine (2012) and Litland (2017) reject it. Thanks to Jon Litland for discussion here.

  24. Schaffer (2009: 374).

  25. See Fine (2012: 52). Fine uses ‘grounding’ for metaphysical explanation, rather than the underlying relation, but this is irrelevant to the point I’m making.

  26. See Kim (1994: 67), Markosian (2005: §3), and Cameron (2014). Wilson (2014: 539) considers the more restricted causal composition relation explanatory.

  27. Relevant implication is not only unnecessary but also insufficient for explanation; see Salmon (1977/1997: 95).

  28. Perhaps causation is an exception, and only non-causal explanatory relations are hyperintensional; this doesn’t matter for the argument. For versions of the “Coarse-grainedness” worry, see Schaffer (2009: 364, 2016: 52), Raven (2015: 325), Bliss and Trogdon (2016: §4), and McKenzie (2014, forthcoming).

  29. Thanks to an anonymous referee for helping me clarify the argument here.

  30. GC could be fine-tuned to accommodate intuitively explanatory relations between entities that cannot themselves stand in the explanation relation, but since I chose to focus on fact-supervenience, I will forgo this task here.

  31. Cf. Audi (2012: 687–688), Schaffer (2009: 364–365, 2016: f52), Rosen (2010: 110–114), and Fine (2012: 41).

  32. Ruben (1990: Ch. 5, Ch. 7: 187–193).

  33. See Strevens (2008: 46) for this example.

  34. See Lipton (2001: 49). See also Kovacs (2017b) for more on these cases.

  35. Shoemaker (2007: 13ff). This is one version of the “subset account of realization”, which has first been formulated by Wilson (1999). I use Shoemaker’s version rather than Wilson’s because it better illustrates the kind of conflation I’m talking about.

  36. I think that a similar difficulty besets a strategy that is the mirror image of the one I considered above: that of playing up the explanatory relevance of causes. This is the route chosen by Skow (2016a), who rejects putative counterexamples to GC by appealing to the pragmatics of explanation. The basic idea is that explanations are answers to ‘Why?’-questions; therefore, a counterexample would be a case in which citing a cause of e in response to ‘Why did e occur?’ would fail to answer the question. Skow argues that all instances of this can be explained away as cases where citing a cause does provide an answer, just not the one we were looking for. However, I doubt this strategy succeeds, since I think that both ‘Why?’-questions and the ‘because’-statements that answer them are ambiguous between causation and causal explanation (see Strawson 1985). As a result, while there is a reading on which ‘c caused e’ implies ‘e occurred because c occurred’, and also a reading on which ‘e occurred because c occurred’ implies ‘the occurrence of c explains the occurrence of e’, I deny that there is any reading on which ‘c caused e’ automatically implies ‘the occurrence of c explains the occurrence of e’. It’s worth noting that in the background there is a deeper disagreement between Skow and me. Elsewhere, Skow (2016b: Ch. 1) argues that instead of theorizing about explanation, philosophers should have been focusing on ‘Why?’-questions from the get-go. I disagree; I take explanation to be the better understood of the two notions, which makes me skeptical of calls to restructure our inquiries around ‘Why?’-questions.

  37. This possibility was suggested to me by an anonymous referee.

  38. See Kim (1988/1993: 167) and Horgan (1993).

  39. This example is taken from Kim (1998: 84ff).

  40. See also Koslicki (2004: 336 n13–14) and Melnyk (2003: Chs. 1–2), respectively, for similar remarks on constitution and realization.

  41. Ehring (2011: Ch. 5), for instance, understands realization in terms of the subclass relation (which according to him is a special case of parthood) between classes of tropes. He even explicitly offers this account as a “metaphysical explanation for why the sets of causal powers of mental properties stand in the subset relation to the sets of causal powers of certain physical properties—the core of the realization relation, according to the Subset Account” (172, emphasis in the original).

  42. I borrow this characterization from [Kelly Trogdon, p.c.]; Jackson and Pettit don’t themselves provide a precise definition of programming.

  43. See Rosen (2010), Audi (2012) and Dasgupta (2014) for similar views; cf. Fine (2012) and Correia (2013).

  44. I’m grateful to Alex Skiles, who forced me to recognize the difference between the "Surface Explanation" and the "Superficial Explanation" worries.

  45. See Schnieder (2010, 2015) and Kovacs (2017b) for this interpretation of ‘backing’-talk.

  46. Some deny that grounding is transitive, and presumably they would deny the transitivity of non-causal explanation, too (Schaffer 2012). But even if they are right, it’s fairly plausible that the particular cases I’m discussing here are transitive.

  47. This question was first raised by Sider (2011: 106–111) and Bennett (2011).

  48. See Jones (ms).

  49. See Bennett (2011) and deRosset (2013). Litland (2017) argues that the grounding (understood as metaphysical explanation) facts are zero-grounded in the empty set of facts, but emphasizes that his view isn’t in competition with the Bennett-deRosset account.

  50. See Dasgupta (2014); cf. Rosen (2010: 130–133) and Audi (2012).

  51. See Sider (ms); cf. Wilson (2014) and Kovacs (2017b).

  52. See Stratton-Lake and Hooker (2006); cf. Zangwill (1997).

  53. See Conee and Feldman (2004).

References

  • Audi, P. (2012). Grounding: Toward a theory of the in-virtue-of relation. Journal of Philosophy, 109, 685–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2004). Global supervenience and dependence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68, 501–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011). By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 27–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2017). The unity of grounding. Mind. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzw069.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1985/1993). Supervenience revisited. Reprinted in Essays on quasi-realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bliss, R. (2014). Viciousness and circles of ground. Metaphilosophy, 45, 245–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bliss, R., & Trogdon, K. (2016). Metaphysical grounding. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/grounding/.

  • Cameron, R. P. (2014). Parts generate the whole, but they are not identical to it. In D. Baxter & A. Cotnoir (Eds.), Composition as identity (pp. 90–107). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleve, V. (1985). Epistemic supervenience and the circle of belief. Monist, 68, 90–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2005). Existential dependence and cognate notions. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2008). Ontological dependence. Philosophy Compass, 3, 1013–1032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2013). Metaphysical grounds and essence. In M. Hoeltje, B. Schnieder, & A. Steinberg (Eds.), Varieties of dependence (pp. 271–296). München: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F., & Schnieder, B. (Eds.). (2012). Grounding: An opinionated introduction. In Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 1–36). Cambridge University Press.

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). The possibility of physicalism. Journal of Philosophy, 111, 557–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970/1980). Mental events. In Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • DePaul, M. (1987). Moral supervenience and dependence. Philosophical Studies, 51, 425–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • deRosset, L. (2010). Getting priority straight. Philosophical Studies, 149, 73–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • deRosset, L. (2013). Grounding explanations. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(7), 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehring, D. (2011). Tropes: Properties, objects, and mental causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, R. (2016). Functionalism, superduperfunctionalism, and physicalism: Lessons from supervenience. Synthese, 193, 2205–2235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1(1), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality (pp. 37–80). Cambridge University Press.

  • Grimes, T. (1988). The myth of supervenience. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 69, 152–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimes, T. (1991). Supervenience, dependency, and determination. Philosophical Studies, 62, 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guigon, G. (2017). Truths qua Grounds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12372.

  • Hare, R. M. (1952). The language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, V., & Newen, A. (2007). Supervenience of extrinsic properties. Erkenntnis, 67, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1982). Supervenience and microphysics. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1993). From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world. Mind, 102, 555–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (1992). Troubles on moral twin earth. Synthese, 92, 221–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990). Program explanation: A general perspective. Analysis, 50, 107–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, N. K. (ms). Ungrounded ground.

  • Kim, J. (1988/1993). Supervenience for multiple domains. In Supervenience and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence. Philosophical Issues, 5, 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klagge, J. (1988). Supervenience: Ontological or Ascriptive. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 66, 461–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2004). Constitution and similarity. Philosophical Studies, 117, 327–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2013). Ontological dependence: An opinionated survey. In M. Hoeltje, B. Schnieder, & A. Steinberg (Eds.), Varieties of dependence: Ontological dependence, grounding, supervenience, response-dependence. München: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2014). The coarse-grainedness of grounding. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 9, 306–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovacs, D. M. (2017a). What is wrong with self-grounding? Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9934-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovacs, D. M. (2017b). Grounding and the argument from explanatoriness. Philosophical Studies, 174, 2927–2952.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kovacs, D. M. (2018). The deflationary theory of ontological dependence. Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqy003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2001). What good is an explanation? In G. Hon & S. S. Rakover (Eds.), Explanation: Theoretical approaches and application. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litland, J. (2017). Grounding ground. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 10, 279–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2005). Against ontological fundamentalism. Facta Philosophica, 7, 69–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, K. (2014). Priority and particle physics: Ontic structural realism as a fundamentality thesis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, K. (2017). Structuralism in the idiom of determination. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx061.

  • McLaughlin, B. (1995). Varieties of supervenience. In E. E. Savellos & U. Yalcin (Eds.), Supervenience: New essays (pp. 16–59). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B., & Bennett, K. (2018). Supervenience. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/supervenience/.

  • Melnyk, A. (2003). A physicalist manifesto: Thoroughly modern materialism. Cambridge: Cambrdige University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petrie, B. (1987). Global supervenience and reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 48, 119–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raven, M. (2012). In defence of ground. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 687–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raven, M. (2015). Ground. Philosophy Compass, 10, 322–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. (2007). Anti-reductionism and supervenience. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4, 330–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruben, D.-H. (1990). Explaining explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1977/1997). A third dogma of empiricism. Reprinted in Causality and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. J. Chalmers, D. Manley & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2012). Grounding, transitivity, and contrastivity. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 122–138). Cambridge University Press.

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies, 173, 49–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2010). A puzzle about ‘Because’. Logique et Analyse, 53, 317–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2015). The asymmetry of ‘Because’. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 91, 131–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2017). Grounding and dependence. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1378-z.

  • Shagrir, O. (2002). Global supervenience, coincident entities and anti-individualism. Philosophical Studies, 109, 171–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O., & Hoffman-Kolss, V. (2013). Supervenience. In B. Kaldis (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of philosophy and the social sciences. Oxford: SAGE Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (1999). Global supervenience and identity across times and worlds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59, 913–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (ms). Ground grounded.

  • Skiles, A. (2015). Against grounding necessitarianism. Erkenntnis, 80, 717–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2016a). Against understanding (as a condition on explanation). In S. Grimm (Ed.), Making sense of the world: New essays on the philosophy of understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2016b). Reasons why. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stratton-Lake, P., & Hooker, B. (2006). Scanlon vs. Moore on goodness. In T. Horgan & M. Timmons (Eds.), Metaethics after Moore. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1985). Causation and explanation. In B. Vermazen & M. Hintikka (Eds.), Essays on Davidson: Actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. E., & Lowe, E. J. (2016). Ontological dependence. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/dependence-ontological/.

  • Trogdon, K. (2013). An introduction to grounding. In M. Hoeltje, B. Schnieder, & A. Steinberg (Eds.), Varieties of dependence (pp. 97–122). München: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trogdon, K. (2017). Grounding-mechanical explanation. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0911-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (1999). How super-duper does a physicalist supervenience need to be. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2014). No work for a theory of grounding. Inquiry, 57, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (1997). Explaining supervenience: Moral and mental. Journal of Philosophical Research, 22, 509–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful comments on and conversations about earlier versions of this paper I thank Karen Bennett, Nina Emery, Ghislain Guigon, Terry Horgan, Jon Litland, Mike Raven, Oron Shagrir, Alex Skiles, Elanor Taylor, Jessica Wilson, three anonymous referees, and audiences at the 2017 Central APA in Kansas City, the Third Annual Conference of the Society for the Metaphysics of Science at Fordham University, and talks given at the Ben Gurion University of the Negev, the University of Southampton, and the Research Group for the History and Philosophy of Science (RCH HAS) in Budapest.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Mark Kovacs.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kovacs, D.M. The myth of the myth of supervenience. Philos Stud 176, 1967–1989 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1106-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1106-7

Keywords

Navigation