Skip to main content
Log in

Actual utility, the mismatch problem, and the move to expected utility

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The mismatch problem for consequentialism arises whenever the theory delivers mismatched verdicts between a group act and the individual acts that compose it. A natural thought is that moving to expected utility versions of consequentialism will solve this problem. I explain why the move to expected utility is not successful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the seminal discussion of this problem, see Parfit (1984).

  2. Jackson (1997) mentions this approach explicitly in connection with Two Shooters. Many others defend the approach in related cases. Like Two Shooters, voting cases involve an overdetermined bad outcome. Suppose that an inferior candidate wins an election by many votes. Parfit (1984, 73–74) argues that consequentialists should appeal to expected utility to explain why individuals act wrongly in voting for the inferior candidate. Factory farming also involves an overdetermined bad outcome. Suppose the same number of animals will be factory-farmed for meat whether I purchase factory-farmed chicken today. Singer (1980), Norcross (2004, 232–233) and Kagan (2011) argue that consequentialists should appeal to expected utility to explain why I act wrongly in purchasing factory-farmed chicken. For other arguments that make an appeal to expected utility in connection with bad outcomes brought about by groups, see Gibbard (19990, 26–27) and Regan (2000, 69–70).

  3. Frank Jackson accepts this framework in Jackson (1987). So does Wlodzimierz Rabinowicz in Rabinowicz (1988).

  4. Why the appeal to compossibility? Suppose you and I are at the salon. I can fit into the tanning booth, and you can fit into the tanning booth, but we cannot both fit into the tanning booth. So if we both opt out of using the tanning booth, it doesn’t follow that [I use the tanning booth, you use the tanning booth] is one of our alternatives. It is not a compossible combination of your and my individual alternatives. In this paper, all the examples will be ones for which all sets of individual alternatives are compossible.

  5. For arguments that some group acts are morally wrong, see Jackson (1987) and Killoren and Williams (2013).

  6. I take this formulation of expected utility from Feldman (2006).

  7. There’s also a temporal dimension to \(Pr(O_{i} \mid a)\) that’s important to keep in mind. Suppose we operate under the credential interpretation of expected utility. Then \(Pr(O_{i} \mid a)\) may vary through time. I might believe firmly in the proposition \(O_{i}\) occurs given that I do a one moment, but become doubtful about this same thing just a moment later. In Two Shooters, I might have a credence of .99 in the proposition the victim dies given that I holster my weapon before you shoot the victim, and a credence of 1 in this same proposition after you in fact shoot him. For this reason, I will assume that the calculation of expected utilities in Two Shooters is to occur in the moments before we fire our weapons.

  8. Since the conditional probabilities are the same on you shoot and you holster respectively, the expected utilities will be the same for you shoot and you holster, respectively. So we have to run the calculation only once.

  9. There’s another version of Two Shooters that gives rise to the mismatch problem under the credential interpretation of expected utility: imagine that each of us is certain that the other will shoot. See Nefsky (2012) and Pinkert (2015). In response to such a case, Kagan (2011) concedes that the move to expected utility is supposed to work only under the condition of individual uncertainty. Two Shooters+ meets the condition of individual uncertainty and yet still gives rise to the mismatch problem for EUAC.

  10. I take it that this is a natural assumption. See, for example, Hylland and Zeckhauser (1979, 1323).

  11. I must note here that I cannot see how any special difficulties will arise in connection with the assignment of objective probabilities to group acts. You and I might have different credences in a conditional on b, and you and I might have different bodies of evidence justifying a conditional on b, but the objective probability of a conditional on b cannot differ between us. Thus, I see no reason to worry about the attributions of conditional probabilities in Two Shooters under the objective intepretation of expected utility.

References

  • Feldman, F. (2006). Actual utility, the objection from impracticality, and the move to expected utility. Philosophical Studies, 129, 49–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Utilitarianism and coordination. New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hylland, A., & Zeckhauser, R. (1979). The impossibility of Bayesian group decision making with separate aggregation of beliefs and values. Econometrica, 47(6), 1321–1336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1987). Group morality. In J. Smart, P. Pettit, R. Sylvan, & J. Norman (Eds.), Metaphysics and morality: Essays in honour of J.J.C. Smart. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1997). Which effects? In J. Dancy (Ed.), Reading Parfit (pp. 42–53). New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (2011). Do I make a difference? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39(2), 105–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Killoren, D., & Williams, B. (2013). Group agency and overdetermination. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, 295–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nefsky, J. (2012). Consequentialism and the problem of collective harm: A reply to Kagan. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39(4), 364–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (2004). Puppies, pigs, and people: Eating meat and marginal cases. Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 229–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkert, F. (2015). What if I cannot make a difference (and know it). Ethics, 125(4), 971–998.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz, W. (1988). Act-utilitarian prisoner’s dilemmas. Theoria, 55(1), 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regan, D. H. (2000). Perceiving imperceptible harms (with other thoughts on transitivity, cumulative effects, and consequentialism). In M. J. Almeida (Ed.), Imperceptible harms and benefits (pp. 49–73). Berlin: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1980). Utilitarianism and vegetarianism. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9(4), 325–337.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’d like to thank the audiences at graduate conferences at the University of Utah and Syracuse University for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this essay. I’d also like to thank participants in the UMass dissertation seminar. For their help with this version of the paper, special thanks goes to Christopher Meacham, Peter Graham, Tricia Magalotti, Miles Tucker, Luis Oliveira, and Scott Hill. I’m especially grateful to Fred Feldman for his invaluable help on this project.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Gruber.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gruber, R. Actual utility, the mismatch problem, and the move to expected utility. Philos Stud 174, 3097–3108 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0848-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0848-3

Keywords

Navigation