Skip to main content
Log in

Why the generality problem is everybody’s problem

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The generality problem is widely considered to be a devastating objection to reliabilist theories of justification. My goal in this paper is to argue that a version of the generality problem applies to all plausible theories of justification. Assume that any plausible theory must allow for the possibility of reflective justification—S’s belief, B, is justified on the basis of S’s knowledge that she arrived at B as a result of a highly (but not perfectly) reliable way of reasoning, R. The generality problem applies to all cases of reflective justification: Given that B is the product of a process-token that is an instance of indefinitely many belief-forming process-types (or BFPTs), why is the reliability of R, rather than the reliability of one of the indefinitely many other BFPTs, relevant to B’s justificatory status? This form of the generality problem is restricted because it applies only to cases of reflective justification. But unless it is solved, the generality problem haunts all plausible theories of justification, not just reliabilist ones.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Others have made similar points. For example, Heller (1995) and Adler and Levin (2002) argue that the generality problem arises for more than just reliabilism. Comesaña (2006) argues that “the problem with the characterization of well-foundedness is intuitively the same as the generality problem, and so any theory that incorporates the notion of well-foundedness into the characterization of justification will have to deal with the generality problem” (p. 31). The argument I propose here, while similar in spirit to the arguments proposed by these authors, is different in detail and broader in scope.

  2. The assumption that a solution to the generality problem must identify a single relevant BFPT has been denied by Wallis (1994) and Wunderlich (2003). I propose to grant it for the sake of argument.

  3. What if someone takes a belief’s justificatory status to be a function of the reliability of its production but is mistaken—it is a function of something else? It doesn’t matter. The generality problem arises for that attempt to show that the belief is justified—even if that attempt is ultimately doomed.

  4. Actually, I will take this back in the next section. Insofar as Sandra’s beliefs about the reliability of the heart attack model are the result of testimony from experts she knows (or justifiably believes) are highly reliable, the generality problem arises for these beliefs as well.

  5. Testimonial knowledge has received considerable attention recently. (For an excellent overview of the literature, see Lackey 2006.) Perhaps the central issue concerning testimonial knowledge is whether testimonial beliefs are (in some sense) epistemically basic. I take no stand on that issue. My thesis requires only the uncontroversial claim that some testimonial beliefs can be justified by explicit, second-order knowledge that the testimony comes from a highly reliable source.

  6. This argument takes advantage of Feldman and Conee’s permissive view of BFPTs: A BFPT is any set of belief-forming process-tokens that share some property or properties.

  7. John Pollock suggested this reply in conversation.

  8. The referee suggested this reply.

  9. Nothing of substance turns on this broader characterization of the generality problem. Those who want to insist that the generality problem applies by definition only when J is the reliability of the relevant BFPTs can call the broader problem the generality problem*. Given that way of describing things, my thesis is that all plausible theories of justification suffer from the generality problem* and this problem is at least as knotty as the generality problem.

References

  • Adler, J., & Levin, M. (2002). Is the generality problem too general? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(1), 87–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1995). How to think about reliability. Philosophical Topics, 23(1), 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. R. (2004). The generality problem, statistical relevance and the tri-level hypothesis. Noûs, 38(1), 177–195.

  • Breiman, L., Friedman, J., Olshen, R., & Stone, C. (1984). Classification and regression trees. Monterey, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comesaña, J. (2006). A well-founded solution to the generality problem. Philosophical Studies, 129, 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1998). The generality problem for reliabilism. Philosophical Studies, 89, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (1985). Reliability and justification. The Monist, 68, 159–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 15–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (2002). Typing problems. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(1), 98–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golding, J., Limerick, S., & MacFarlane, A. (1985). Sudden infant death. Somerset: Open Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1995). The simple solution to the generality problem. Nous, 29(4), 501–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2006). Introduction. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J., & Cruz, J. (1999). Contemporary theories of knowledge (2nd ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinsey, V. L., Harris, G. T., Rice, M. E., & Cormier, C. A. (1998). Violent offenders: Appraising and managing risk. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, F. (1992). Knowledge and belief. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1985). Knowledge and intellectual virtue. The Monist, 68, 224–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallis, C. (1994). Truth-ratios, process, task, and knowledge. Synthese, 98, 243–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wunderlich, M. (2003). Vector reliability: A new approach to epistemic justification. Synthese, 136, 237–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For many excellent questions on earlier versions of this paper, I would like to thank audiences at the University of Pennsylvania, Stockholm University, the University of Gothenburg, and at the conference on The Epistemology of Natural and Artificial Systems at California State University, Long Beach. I would also like to thank Stewart Cohen, Hilary Kornblith, John Pollock, J.D. Trout, Charles Wallis, an anonymous referee, and especially Mark Wunderlich for very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I am also grateful to the National Science Foundation for grant SES#0354536 that supported this research in its early stages.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael A. Bishop.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bishop, M.A. Why the generality problem is everybody’s problem. Philos Stud 151, 285–298 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9445-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9445-z

Keywords

Navigation