Skip to main content
Log in

Why is a truth-predicate like a pronoun?

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I begin with an exposition of the two main variants of the Prosentential Theory of Truth (PT), those of Dorothy Grover et al. and Robert Brandom. Three main types of criticisms are then put forward: (1) material criticisms to the effect that (PT) does not adequately explain the linguistic data, (2) an objection to the effect that no variant of (PT) gives a properly unified account of the various occurrences of “true” in English, and, most importantly, (3) a charge that the comparison with proforms is explanatorily idle. The last objection is that, given a complete semantic account of pronouns, proadjectives, antecedents, etc., together with a complete (PT), the essential semantic character of “true” could be deduced, but then, the idleness of the comparison with pronouns would be apparent. It turns out that objections (2) and (3) are related in the following way: the prosentential terminology is held to conceal the lack of unity in (PT), by describing the different data in the same terms (“proform”, “antecedent”, etc.). But this, I argue, is only a way of truly describing, rather than explaining, the data, these being certain relations of equivalence and consequence between sentences. I consider a language for which (PT) would be not only true, but also explanatory, but note that this language is very different from English. I end by showing that Robert Brandom’s case that “is true” is not a predicate fails, and that his motivation for saying so is based on fallacious reasoning (namely, Boghossian’s argument against deflationism).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ramsey’s proposal, of course, was “For all a, R, b, if he asserts aRb, then aRb”, but given the obvious limitations of such paraphrases, his view is usually presented as above.

  2. Somewhat confusingly, they previously explained the workings of lazy pronouns by claiming that they take the referent of their antecedent (1975: 85). However, it would seem that since they give a substitutional account of prosentences, other proforms must have such a semantics as well, lest the analogy must be abandoned.

  3. A major motivation for Priorian analyses of such quantified sentences is nominalism. In Båve (2006: Ch. 5), however, it is argued that the naïve, relational syntactic analysis can be had without commitment to propositions. Prior’s analysis is naturally coupled with a conception of singular attitude ascriptions, of the form “x Vs that p” on which “Vs that”, rather than “that p”, is regarded as a syntactic unit, a function from a term and a sentence to a sentence. This idea has its roots in Russell’s “multiple relations” theory (1910), (1912: XII), and similar views have more recently been defended by, e.g., Tye (1989), and Matthews (1994), and it receives a very elaborated treatment in Moltmann (2003).

  4. Brandom also explicitly acknowledges the intersubstitutability of “it is true that p” and “p” in all occurrences (1994: 299f).

  5. Brandom describes other deflationary theories as “cruder” than his own (2002: 119)—as if simplicity were a vice—and then claims that it cannot cover as many types of occurrences of “true” ((1997: 211), (2002: 108)). In fact, however, principle (b) explains every occurrence of “true” with only very plausible or “obvious” assumptions (see Båve 2006: 4.3). Concerning the critique against the prosentential analysis of (1), though, Brandom has more recently (2002) given a syntactic analysis that accords with my own. Here, the role of “is true” in “Everything he says is true” seems to be explained rather by first rephrasing the sentence as “Everything is such that if he says it, then it is true”, and then considering “is true” as having the quote-names instantiating the first “it” as antecedent. For instance, in the instance “If he says ‘Snow is white’, then it is true”, “it is true” is a lazy prosentence and has the quote-name of the sentence “Snow is white” as antecedent (2002: 107). (This idea also seems to extend naturally to cases of indirect speech.) Brandom thus seems to have rid himself of the Ramseyan heritage of the original prosententialists. He also gives a more plausible account of tensed and modified truth-claims (2002: 108), so as to save (PT) from objections on that score (e.g., in Kirkham 1992: 327f), and about anaphoric uses of “that” in truth-claims (i.e. “That is true”). This does not, however, save him from the generic objections against (PT) to be given below.

References

  • Båve, A. (2006). Deflationism: A use-theoretic analysis of the truth-predicate. Ph. D. Thesis, Acta Universitatis Stockholmiensis, Stockholm, Almqvist & Wiksell International.

  • Båve, A. (forthcoming). A deflationary theory of reference. Synthèse.

  • Beebe, J. R. (2006). The prosentential theory of truth. In J. Fieser & B. Dowden (Eds.), The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = http://www.iep.utm.edu/t/truthpro.htm.

  • Boghossian, P. (1990). The status of content. The Philosophical Review, 99, 157–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1997). Replies to commentators. In Villanueva (1997), pp. 199–214.

  • Brandom, R. (2002). Explanatory vs. expressive deflationism about truth. In Schantz (2002), pp. 103–119.

  • Field, H. (1994). Deflationist views about meaning and content. Mind, 103, 249–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2001). Truth and the absence of fact. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grover, D., Camp, J., & Belnap, N. (1975). A prosentential theory of truth. Philosophical Studies, 27, 73–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1998). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkham, R. (1992). Theories of truth. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lance, M. (1997). The significance of anaphoric theories of truth and reference. In Villanueva (1997), pp.181–198.

  • Matthews, F. (1994). The measure of mind. Mind, 103, 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2003). Propositional attitudes without propositions. Synthese, 135, 77–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1971). Objects of thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, V. W. O. (1981). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 7: 153–170.

  • Russell, B. (1910). On the nature of truth and falsehood. In Logical and philosophical papers Vol. 6 1909–13 (1966), New York, Simon and Schuster, pp. 116–124.

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schantz, R. (Eds.). (2002). What is truth? Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1999). Understanding truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1989). The metaphysics of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villanueva, E. (Eds.). (1997). Truth (Philosophical Issues 8). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

  • Wilson, W. K. (1990). Some reflections on the prosentential theory of truth. In Dunn and Gupta (Eds.) (1990), Truth or consequences. Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 19–32.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arvid Båve.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Båve, A. Why is a truth-predicate like a pronoun?. Philos Stud 145, 297–310 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9232-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9232-2

Keywords

Navigation