Skip to main content
Log in

On the content of Peripersonal visual experience

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent paper, ‘Peripersonal perception in action’ (Synthese, 2018), Frédérique de Vignemont tackles the problem of defining what is peculiar to the visual perception of objects falling within the peripersonal space of the observer, i.e. the space immediately surrounding the body, and which is commonly described as the space in which action takes place. In this paper, I first discuss the proposal offered by de Vignemont about what characterizes peripersonal perception. Then, I suggest an extension of this account that offers a meticulous description of the nature of the Content of Peripersonal Visual Experience - a topic never explicitly considered in the philosophical literature on vision - by discussing some peculiar features of it that, as recognized also by de Vignemont’s account, still need to be explained. In particular, I offer a philosophical examination of the specificity of peripersonal visual experience, in relation to its phenomenological dimension, its optical mechanisms and its neurophysiological underpinnings, in the light of our best theories from vision science, and in comparison to the visual experience of other visual spaces.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a recent and critical experimental result concerning  this point see (Di Marco et al. 2019).

  2. Though it is quickly mentioned that dorsal processing can participate in object recognition (Ibid.).

  3. I am not analyzing here the relation between ‘presence’ and ‘reality’, see (Ferretti 2016c, 2018, 2021b; Matthen 2005, 2010).

  4. Interestingly, from an optical point of view (cfr. §3.2), in an experiment assessing the preference of the visual brain for close stimuli, based on depth cues related to the looming effect of the object, “one strong cue to depth was the near response based on oculomotor cues. The near response occurs when subjects gaze at a close object, causing the eyes to rotate inward (convergence), the lens to thicken (accommodation), and the pupils to dilate. These three yoked responses – vergence, accommodation and pupillary diameter – are sometimes referred to as the near triad” (Quinlan and Culham 2007: 168). That said, while the ‘near triad’ is, in standard perceptual cases, usually ‘yoked’, this does not happen necessarily, e.g. in every visual scenario. For example, vergence can be dissociated from accommodation in the case of virtual realities. This is the case discussed by Svarverud et al. (2012), in which participants remain unaware of a 4-fold expansion, in size, of a virtual room (and, thus, in the distance of virtual objects), when the pictorial cues are manipulated in a way that changes related to vergence, accommodation and proprioception (this being related to walking across the room in order to view the object) cannot serve as basis to perceive the size and/or distance of objects. I agree that: “This astonishing lack of awareness of object size and distance is potentially highly informative about the central processing of spatial information” (p.1), as this results tell us something new about possible dissociations of optical mechanisms. That said, the reader should note that the evidence on dissociations in distance cues (and the related impossible non-transitive perceptions of distance that can be produced), does not affect at all the philosophical account presented here, as they are due to special experimental scenarios reached by means of virtual scenes. But the present article is interested in usual cases of standard perception we have in normal conditions. More specifically, even if relying on experiments, it wants to investigate what we can say about peripersonal visual experience in standard perceptual cases, not in cases in which virtual realities are involved. So, the fact that these mechanims can be, in principle, and by means of a virtual reality setting, dissociated does not deny that they are the crucial ingredients, working together in everyday situations, at the basis of the standard optical mechanisms subserving visual experience of presence within peripersonal space.

  5. The account on interstream interplay can also explain how the visual sense of presence can be gradually lost as the object pertains to far space (Ferretti 2016c, 2018; cfr. §4).

  6. For completeness, it is worth mentioning the interesting case of particular frontal lobe deficits, which can lead to the famous ‘utilisation behavior’, which represents an example where the demand character induces the unavoidable urge to act in the patient (see Eslinger 2002).

  7. In accordance with the neurophysiological analysis within the framework of the TVSM, we know of a special relation between action and peripersonal space that is grounded on some structural, anatomo-functional connections between the (parietal-premotor) cortical networks underlying motor action and those underlying peripersonal encoding of reachable space (for a review see Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016; for a philosophical review see Ferretti 2016a, 2016b, 2016c2017c, 2018, 2019b, 2021a).

  8. Here I am endorsing the notion of emotional space in a very broad sense, just reporting the peculiarities, related to emotional encoding, of visual targets located within peripersonal space. In general, when a subject consciously realizes, for example, that a black blob in the visual periphery is a spider, there is a motor reaction that is also emotionally charged at the level of the subject’s consciousness. However, if the spider suddenly and rapidly enters the peripheral visual field, the motor reaction comes much more quickly. This is due to a quick and unconscious emotional encoding of the visual object. In this respect, the conscious aspect of this emotional charge would be added only later. Concerning the orbito-frontal cortex, the studies I report seem to suggest that this encodes, very quickly, stimuli that can have an emotional impact on our perception when it is unconscious and, thus, in principle related to the fast and automatic guidance of motor (re)action. However, it is also responsible for the conscious elaboration of the emotional encoding related to the visual recognition of an object, at a later stage of visual processing. While emotional states can be conscious or unconscious, also the orbito-frontal encoding seems to operate at both levels.

  9. It is not by chance that the visibility of objects presented in the peripersonal space automatically modulates postural behaviors (Bonnet et al. 2010). Furthermore, defensive responses in peripersonal space are not always automatic, but can also be influenced by cognitive evaluations (de Vignemont and Iannetti 2015: Sect. 4).

  10. In line with footnote 7, there is also evidence that the cortical networks involved in defensive and non-defensive behavior are also related, in different manners, to those (parietal-premotor) cortical networks subserving peripersonal encoding and motor interaction (Hunley and Laurenco 2018: 3.3).

  11. While it has been shown that stereopsis could be achieved even in monocular conditions, but in special experimental contexts (Vishwanath 2014; for philosophical discussion, see Ferretti 2016c, 2018, 2021b), stereoblind people cannot achieve it, due to these ocular problems related to the inappropriate motor behavior in the coordination of both eyes.

  12. It would be interesting to consider a Molyneux’s question formulation concerning peripersonal visual experience (and even in relation to stereoblindness), on the basis of what it has been already said in the literature concerning this question and spatial and motor perception (Ferretti, 2017c, 2020b; Ferretti and Glenney 2020).

  13. For a very recent and critical review of the best explanation of the relation between auditory representations and peripersonal space extension, see (Holmes et al. 2020). In this respect, it seems that the nature of the possible auditory representations of distance in the human brain is not very clear. One reason is that it is theoretically very difficult to compute auditory distance in an unambiguous manner. Thus, an alleged auditory dimension of peripersonal space localization would be very different from the visual one. I thank a reviewer for this suggestion.

  14. This is in line with the idea that peripersonal representations are modulated on the basis of knowing-how (Jackson 2014), which could be still present in these cases, even if overt motor execution cannot be performed due to physical problems (see the analysis by Noë 2005).

  15. Of course, while here I am discussing some of the relevant experimental results coming from the empirical literature, there are still some aspects of peripersonal space representations, also related to the perceptual mechanisms reported in this paper, that are under scrutiny within a large neuroscientific debate. In this respect, a final account of the scientific questions concerning the peculiar aspects of peripersonal space discussed in this paper is very desirable, though not available yet, and some of these aspects still are matter of controversy (as, for example, in the case of tool use - for a critical overview see Holmes et al. 2007, Holmes 2012 - or of auditory representations - for a critical overview see Holmes et al. 2020). Just to mention an example here, while, as we saw (§7.2), the hypothesis of an extension of peripersonal space through tool use has been endorsed by several neuroscientists, a critical analysis of this hypothesis has proposed a competing description, according to which using tools does not actually extend peripersonal space representations, but simply fosters an allocation of attention on the spatial region where the tool is manipulated (Holmes et al. 2007).

References

  • Abrams, R. A., Davoli, C. C., Du, F., Knapp, W. H., & Paull, D. (2008). Altered vision near the hands. Cognition, 107(3), 1035–1047.

  • Anelli, F., Borghi, A. M., & Nicoletti, R. (2012). Grasping the pain: Motor resonance with dangerous affordances. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 1627–1639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. F., & Bar, L. F. (2009). See it with feeling: Affective predictions during object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 364, 1325–1334. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2008.0312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, S. (2009). Fixing my gaze. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berti, A., & Frassinetti, F. (2000). When far becomes near: Remapping of space by tool use. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 12(3), 415–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, O., Slater, M., & Serino, A. (2015). Behavioral, neural, and computational principles of bodily self-consciousness. Neuron, 88, 145–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blini, E., Desoche, C., Salemme, R., Kabil, A., Hadj-Bouziane, F., & Farnè, A. (2018). Mind the depth: Visual perception of shapes is better in Peripersonal space. Psychological Science, 29(11), 1868–1877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet, C. T., Temprado, J. J., & Berton, E. (2010). The effects of the proximity of an object on human stance. Gait & Posture, 32(1), 124–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. (2009). Egocentric spatial representation in action and perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 423–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R., & Schwenkler, J. (2015). Conscious vision in action. Cognitive Science, 39(7), 1435–1467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35, 1076–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bufacchi, R. J., Sambo, C.F., Di Stefano, G. Cruccu, G., Iannetti, G.D., (2017). Pain outside the body: Defensive peripersonal space deformation in trigeminal neuralgia. Scientific Reports, 7: 12487. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-017-12466-5.

  • Canzoneri, E., Marzolla, M., Amoresano, A., Verni, G., & Serino, A. (2013). Amputation and prosthesis implantation shape body and peripersonal space representations. Scientific Reports, 3, 2844. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep02844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardellicchio, P., Sinigaglia, C., & Costantini, M. (2011). The space of affordances: A TMS study. Neuropsychologia, 49(5), 1369–1372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardini, F., Fatemi-Ghomi, N., Gajewska-Knapik, K., Gooch, V., Aspell, J.E. (2019). Enlarged representation of peripersonal space in pregnancy, 9:8606, https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-45224-w.

  • Chen, J., Wu, E.-D., Chen, X. Z., L-H, L. X., Thorn, F., Ostrovsky, Y., Qu, J. et al. (2016). Rapid integration of tactile and visual information by a newly sighted child. Current Biology, 26(8), 1069–1074.

  • Chinellato E., Ferretti G., Irving L. (2019). Affective Visuomotor Interaction: A Functional Model for Socially Competent Robot Grasping. In: Martinez-Hernandez U. et al. (eds) Biomimetic and Biohybrid Systems. Living Machines 2019. Lecture notes in computer science, vol 11556. Springer, Cham.

  • Chinellato, E., & del Pobil, A. P. (2016). The visual neuroscience of robotic grasping. Achieving sensorimotor skills through dorsal-ventral stream integration. Berlin: Springer International Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110(4), 495–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Combe, E., & Fujii, N. (2011). Depth perception and defensive system activation in a 3-d environment. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costantini, M., Ambrosini, E., Scorolli, C., & Borghi, A. M. (2011). When objects are close to me: Affordances in the peripersonal space. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 18, 302–308. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-011-0054-4.

  • Costantini, M., Ambrosini, E., Tieri, G., Sinigaglia, C., & Committeri, G. (2010). Where does an object trigger an action? An investigation about affordance in space. Experimental Brain Research, 207, 95–103.

  • Cutting, J. E., & Vishton, P. M. (1995). Perceiving layout and knowing distances: The integration, relative potency, and contextual use of different information about depth. In W. Epstein & S. J. Rogers (Eds.), Perception of space and motion (pp. 69–117). San Diego: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Haan, E. H. F., Jackson, S. T., & Schenk, T. (2018). Where are we now with ‘what’ and ‘how’? Cortex, 98(1), 7–140. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rehab.2017.02.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Vignemont, F. (2018). Peripersonal perception in action. Synthese. Special issue: Between Vision and Action, (Eds.) Ferretti G., and Zipoli Caiani, S. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01962-4.

  • de Vignemont, F., & Iannetti, G. D. (2015). How many peripersonal spaces? Neuropsychologia, 70, 327–334. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2014.11.018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Marco, S., Tosoni, A., Altomare, E. C., Ferretti, G., Perrucci, M. G., & Committeri, G. (2019). Walking-related locomotion is facilitated by the perception of distant targets in the extrapersonal space. Scientific Reports, 9, 9884. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-46384-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’angelo, M., di Pellegrino, G., Seriani, S., Gallina, P., & Frassinetti, F. (2018). The sense of agency shapes body schema and peripersonal space. Scientific Reports, 8, 13847. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-018-32238-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dufour, A., & Touzalin, P. (2008). Improved visual sensitivity in the perihand space. Experimental Brain Research, 190(1), 91–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eslinger, P. J. (2002). The anatomic basis of utilisation behaviour: A shift from frontal-parietal to intra-frontal mechanisms. Cortex, 38(3), 273–276. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-9452(08)70658-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farivar, R. (2009). Dorsal–ventral integration in object recognition. Brain Research Reviews, 61(2), 144–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti G. and Chinellato E. (2019). Can our robots rely on an emotionally charged vision-for-action? An embodied model for Neurorobotics. In: Vallverdú J., Müller V. (eds) Blended Cognition, The Robotic Challenge. Springer series in cognitive and neural systems, vol 12. Springer, Cham.

  • Ferretti G. and Zipoli Caiani S. (2019). Between vision and action. Introduction to the Special Issue. Synthese, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02518-w.

  • Ferretti, G. (2016a). Pictures, action properties and motor related effects. Synthese, Special Issue: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1097-x.

  • Ferretti, G. (2016b). Through the forest of motor representations. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 177–196. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.05.013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016c). Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly., 99, 112–136. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017a). Pictures, emotions, and the dorsal/ventral account of picture perception. Review of Philosophy and Psychology., 8, 595–616. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0330-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017b). Are pictures peculiar objects of perception? Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(3), 372–393. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2017.28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017c). Two visual Systems in Molyneux Subjects. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(4), 643–679. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9533-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2018). The neural dynamics of seeing-in. Erkenntnis, 84, 1285–1324. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0060-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2019a). Perceiving surfaces (and what they depict). In Glenney B. & J. F. Silva (Eds.), the senses and the history of philosophy, London: Routledge.

  • Ferretti, G. (2019b). Visual phenomenology versus Visuomotor imagery: How can we be aware of action properties? Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02282-x.

  • Ferretti, G. (2020a). Why Trompe l’oeils deceive our visual experience. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 78-1, 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2020b). Action at first sight. In Ferretti, G. and Glenney, B. (Eds.). Molyneux’s Question and the History of Philosophy, Routledge.

  • Ferretti, G. (2020c). Do Trompe l’Oeils Look Right When Viewed from the Wrong Place? The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 78(3), 319–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2020d). Anti-intellectualist motor knowledge. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02750-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2021a). A distinction concerning vision-for-action and affordance perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 87, 103028.

  • Ferretti, G. (2021b). Why the Pictorial needs the Motoric. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00381-1.

  • Ferretti, G. and Glenney, B. (2020). Molyneux’s question and the history of philosophy. Routledge.

  • Ferretti, G., & Marchi, F. (2020). Visual attention in pictorial perception. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02873-z.

  • Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (2018). Solving the Interface problem without translation: The same format thesis. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 100, 301–333. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (2021). Habitual Actions, Propositional Knowledge, Motor Representations and Intentionality. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-020-09723-0.

  • Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (Forthcoming). How Knowing-That and Knowing-How Interface in Action: The Intelligence of Motor Representations. Erkenntnis.

  • Foley, T. R., Whitwell, R. L., & Goodale, M. A. (2015). The two-visual-systems hypothesis and the perspectival features of visual experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 35(2015), 225–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2007). The “conscious” dorsal stream: Embodied simulation and its role in space and action conscious awareness. Psyche, 13(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Sinigaglia, C. (2010). The bodily self as power for action. Neuropsychologia, 48, 746–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and Sinigaglia C., (2011). How the Body in Action Shapes the Self. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18, 7–8, 2011, pp. 117–43.

  • Goodhew, S. C., Edwards, M., Ferber, S., & Pratt, J. (2015). Altered visual perception near the hands: A critical review of attentional and neurophysiological models. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 55, 223–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gozli, D. G., West, G. L., & Pratt, J. (2012). Hand position alters vision by biasing processing through different visual pathways. Cognition, 124(2), 244–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graziano, M.S. & Cooke, D. F. (2006). Parieto-frontal interactions, personal space, and defensive behavior. Neuropsychologia 44, 845–859.

  • Graziano, M. (2009). The intelligent movement machine: An ethological perspective on the primate motor system. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2007). Skill theory v2.0: Dispositions, emulation, and spatial perception. Synthese, 159(3), 389–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, N. P., Sanabria, D., Calvert, G. A., & Spence, C. (2007). Tool-use: Capturing multisensory spatial attention or extending multisensory peripersonal space? Cortex, 43(3), 469–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, N. P. (2012). Does tool use extend peripersonal space? A review and re-analysis. Experimental Brain Research, 218, 273–282. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-012-3042-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, N. P., Martin, D., Mitchell, W., Noorani, Z., & Thorne, A. (2020). Do sounds near the hand facilitate tactile reaction times? Four experiments and a meta-analysis provide mixed support and suggest a small effect size. Experimental Brain Research, 238, 995–1009. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-020-05771-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunley, S. B., & Lourenco, S. F. (2018). What is peripersonal space? An examination of unresolved empirical issues and emerging findings. WIREs Cogn Sci, 9, e1472. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcs.1472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iachini, T., Ruggiero, G., Ruotolo, F., & Vinciguerra, M. (2014). Motor resources in peripersonal space are intrinsic to spatial encoding: Evidence from motor interference. Acta Psychologica, 153, 20–27. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.actpsy.2014.09.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iachini, T., Ruotolo, F., Vinciguerra, M., & Ruggiero, G. (2017). Manipulating time and space: Collision prediction in peripersonal and extrapersonal space. Cognition, 166, 107–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, G. B. (2014). Skillful action in peripersonal space. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Science., 13, 313–334. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9301-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. P., & Brockmole, J. R. (2014). Hand proximity differentially affects visual working memory for color and orientation in a binding task. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2010). Two visual systems and the feeling of presence. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spencer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness: Sensorimotor Dynamics and the Two Visual Systems (pp. 107–124). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Milner, A., & Goodale, M. (1995/2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2008). Two visual systems re-viewed. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 774–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2011). Perceiving pictures. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10, 461–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013). Between perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nijboer, T. C. W., Ten Brink, A. F., Kouwenhoven, M., & Visser-Meily, J. M. A. (2014). Functional assessment of region-specific neglect: Are there differential behavioural consequences of peripersonal versus extrapersonal neglect? Behavioural Neurology, 2014, 526407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2005). Against intellectualism. Analysis, 65, 278–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noel, J.-P., Pfeiffer, C., Blanke, O., & Serino, A. (2015). Peripersonal space as the space of the bodily self. Cognition, 144, 49–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2015.07.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orioli, G. Santoni, A. Dragovic, D. and Farroni, T. (2019). Identifying peripersonal space boundaries in newborns. Scientific reports, 9:9370 | https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-45084-4.

  • Quinlan, D. J., & Culham, J. C. (2007). fMRI reveals a preference for near viewing in the human parieto-occipital cortex. NeuroImage, 36(1), 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ravenscroft, J. (2019). (Eds.) The Routledge handbook of visual impairment. Routledge.

  • Reed, C. L., Betz, R., Garza, J. P., & Roberts, R. J. (2010). Grab it! Biased attention in functional hand and tool space. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 72(1), 236–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C. L., Grubb, J. D., & Steele, C. (2006). Hands up: Attentional prioritization of space near the hand. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 32(1), 166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (1997). The space around us. Science, 277, 190–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serino, A. (2019). Peripersonal space (PPS) as a multisensory interface between the individual and the environment, defining the space of the self. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 99, 138–159. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.01.016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2014). Affordances and the contents of perception. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content? (pp. 51–75). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Svarverud, E., Gilson, S., & Glennerster, A. (2012). A demonstration of ‘broken’ visual space. PLoS One, 7(3), e33782. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0033782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uji, M., Jentzsch, I., Redburn, J., & Vishwanath, D. (2019a). Dissociating neural activity associated with the subjective phenomenology of monocular stereopsis: An EEG study. Neuropsychologia, 129, 357–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uji, M., Lingnau, A., Cavin, I., & Vishwanath, D. (2019b). Identifying Cortical Substrates Underlying the Phenomenology of Stereopsis and Realness: A Pilot fMRI Study. Front Neurosci, 13, 646. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2019.00646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D. (2011). Information in surface and depth perception: Reconciling pictures and reality. In L. Albertazzi, G. J. van Tonder, & D. Vishwanath (Eds.), Perception beyond inference. The information content of visual processes (pp. 201–240). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D. (2014). Toward a new theory of stereopsis. Psychological Review, 121(2), 151–178.

  • Vishwanath, D., & Hibbard, P. (2010). Quality in depth perception: The plastic effect. Journal of Vision, 10. https://doi.org/10.1167/10.7.42.

  • Vishwanath, D., & Hibbard, P. (2013). Seeing in 3D with just one eye: Stereopsis in the absence of binocular disparities. Psychological Science, 24, 1673–1685.

  • Zipoli Caiani, S., & Ferretti, G. (2017). Semantic and pragmatic integration in vision for action. Consciousness and Cognition, 48, 40–54. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.10.009.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to warmly thank two anonymous reviewers and Nick Holmes for addressing important comments, both on the experimental and on the philosophical side, which led me to significantly improve the first version of this article. I would also like to thank Silvano Zipoli Caiani, Anna Borghi, Giorgia Committeri, Eris Chinellato, Vittorio Gallese, Albert Newen, and Bence Nanay for offering interesting conversations on the topics addressed in the present article. Since the finalization of the work for the publication of the present article has been done during the transition from one research position to another, I would like to acknowledge support from both the corresponding fellowships. This work was supported by a NOMIS Fellowship, awarded by the Eikones - Center for the Theory and History of the Image at the University of Basel, Switzerland. This work was also supported by a Humboldt Fellowship, hosted by Professor Albert Newen at the Institute for Philosophy II, Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabriele Ferretti.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ferretti, G. On the content of Peripersonal visual experience. Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 487–513 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09733-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09733-2

Keywords

Navigation