Skip to main content
Log in

Review of Transcendental Philosophy and Naturalism

Joel Smith & Peter Sullivan (Eds) Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (Oxford University Press, Oxford), 2011, vii-212

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. Lear appeals to Wittgenstein’s later work, particularly the rule-following considerations of Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein 1953).

  2. In his chapter, A.W. Moore offers reasons for why we should adopt the second of these two attitudes (Moore 2011).

  3. The argument thus has the form of a transcendental argument. I discuss this issue, as the second major theme of the collection, in more detail below.

  4. “If we were not conscious that what we think is the same as what we thought a moment before, all reproduction in the series of representations would be useless.” (Kant 1781/7:A103)

  5. Kornblith appeals to Skinner and Ferster’s studies of rats and pigeons (Skinner and Ferster 1957), and states that much of the empirical literature regarding animal mechanisms of learning contradicts the anti-naturalist’s inference.

  6. This is particularly true of Sellars’ work and for those who appropriate his notion of ‘the space of reasons’ (see, for example, (McDowell 1996) and (Brandom 1994 & 2000)).

References

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 47, 5–20. Reprinted in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, (pp. 183–98). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001.

  • Haddock, A. (2011). Davidson and idealism. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 26–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/7). Critique of pure reason. Translated by N. Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan Press, 1929

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). The Unity of Kant’s Active Thinker. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 55–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2011). Reasons, naturalism, and transcendental philosophy. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 96–119). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lear, J. (1982). Leaving the world alone. Journal of Philosophy, 79, 382–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2011). Naturalism, transcendentalism, and therapy. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 120–156). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world, with a new introduction by the author. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A. W. (2011). Vats, sets, and tits. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 41–54). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F., & Ferster, C. (1957). Schedules of reinforcement. New York: Appleton Century Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2011). Strawson on other minds. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 184–208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J., & Sullivan, P. (2011). Introduction: Transcendental philosophy and naturalism. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 1–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, R. (2011). The value of humanity: Reflections on Korsgaard’s transcendental argument. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 74–95). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (1968). Transcendental arguments. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, P. (2011). Is logic transcendental? In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Transcendental philosophy and naturalism (pp. 157–183). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. London: Blackwell

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dominic Shaw.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shaw, D. Review of Transcendental Philosophy and Naturalism . Phenom Cogn Sci 11, 423–430 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-012-9255-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-012-9255-1

Navigation