Skip to main content
Log in

The roots of self-awareness

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we provide an account of the structural underpinnings of self-awareness. We offer both an abstract, logical account – by way of suggestions for how to build a genuinely self-referring artificial agent – and a biological account, via a discussion of the role of somatoception in supporting and structuring self-awareness more generally. Central to the account is a discussion of the necessary motivational properties of self-representing mental tokens, in light of which we offer a novel definition of self-representation. We also discuss the role of such tokens in organizing self-specifying information, which leads to a naturalized restatement of the guarantee that introspective awareness is immune to error due to mis-identification of the subject.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson, M. L. 2003a. Embodied cognition: A field guide. Artificial Intelligence 149(1): 91–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. 2003b. Representations, symbols and embodiment. Artificial Intelligenc. 149(1): 151–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. 1963. Intention, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M., Pook, P. K. and Rao, R. P. N. 1997. Deictic codes for the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20(4): 723–742.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1989. The autistic child's theory of mind: A case of specific developmental delay. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 30: 285–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1991. Precursors to a theory of mind: understanding attention in others. In: A. Whiten (ed), Natural Theories of Mind: Evolution, Development, and Simulation of Everyday Mindreading, pp. 233–251. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1994. How to build a baby that can read minds: Cognitive mechanisms in mindreading. Current Psychology of Cognition 13: 513–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botvinick, M. and Cohen, J. 1998. Rubber hands ‘feel’ touch that eyes can see. Nature 391: 756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. 1991. Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence 47: 139–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrozzo, M., McIntyre, J., Zago, M. and Lacquaniti, F. 1999. Viewer-centered and body-centered frames of reference in direct visuomotor transformations. Experimental Brain Research 129(2): 201–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 1996a. Autism as mind-blindness: An elaboration and partial defence. In: P. Carruthers and P. K. Smith (eds), Theories of Theories of Mind, pp. 257–273. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 1996b. Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of theory-theory. In: P. Carruthers and P. K. Smith (eds), Theories of Theories of Mind, pp. 22–38. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2002. The cognitive functions of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25(6).

  • Castañeda, H.-N. 1966. ‘He’: a study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio 8: 130–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1995a. Absent qualia, fading qualia, dancing qualia. In: T. Metzinger (ed), Conscious Experience. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1995b. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2: 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1979. On cognitive structures and their development: A reply to Piaget. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (ed), Language and Learning – The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisley, R. 2003. Embodied AI. Artificial Intelligence 149(1): 131–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, J. C. and Rollman, G. B. 1999. Somesthesis. Annual Review of Psychology 50: 305–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, S. 2002. Constraints on the nature of the neural representations of the visual world. Trends in Cognitive Science 6: 125–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrsson, H. H. 2002. Awareness of limb movement: Illusory sensations in the primary motor cortex. Proceedings of Tucson 2002: Towards a Science of Consciousness, pp. 65–66.

  • Fodor, J. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1960. On sense and reference. In: P. Geach and M. Black (eds), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, pp. 56–78. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 1986. Body image and body schema: A conceptual clarification. Journal of Mind and Behavior 7: 541–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2001. The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2003. Bodily self-awareness and object perception. Theoria et Historia Scientarum: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7(1): 53–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2004. Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction theory as an alternative to theory of mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 11(3): 199–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. 1990. The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghez, C., Gordon, J. and Ghilardi, M. F. 1995. Impairments of reaching movements in patients without proprioception. ii. effects of visual information on accuracy. Journal of Neurophysiology 73: 361–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. 1989. Interpretation psychologized. Mind and Language 4: 161–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. 1986. Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language 1: 158–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. 1995. Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you. In: M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hari, R., Hanninen, R., Makinen, T., Jousmaki, V., Forss, N., Seppa, M. and Salonen, O. 1998. Three hands: Fragmentation of human bodily awareness. Neuroscience Letters 240: 131–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. 1986. Replication and runctionalism. In: J. Butterfield (ed), Language, Mind, and Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. 1998a. Co-cognition and off-line simulation: Two ways of understanding the simulation approach. Mind and Language 13: 477–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. 1998b. Understanding other minds from the inside. In: A. O'Hear (ed), Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogan, M. and Martin, R. 2001. Introspective misidentification. In: A. Brook and R. DeVidi (eds), Self-reference and Self-awareness, pp. 205–213. John Benjamins Publishing Company.

  • Humphrey, N. 1992. A History of the Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J. R. 2003. The neural basis of predicate argument structure. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23(6).

  • Kirsh, D. 1991. Today the earwig, tomorrow man? Artificial Intelligence 47(3): 161–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. 1994. ToMM, ToBy and Agency: Core architecture and domain specificity. In: L. A. Hirschfeld and S. A. Gelman (eds), Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture, pp. 119–148. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. 2000. How to acquire a ‘representational theory of mind’. In: D. Sperber (ed), Metarepresentations: A Multidisciplinary Perspective, pp. 197–223. Ablex Publishing.

  • Marr, D. 1982. Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. New York: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. 1990. The myth of the essential indexical. Noûs. 24: 723–734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. 1996. Pushmi-pullyu representations. In: L. May and M. Friedman (eds), Mind and Morals, pp. 145–161. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D. and Goodale, M. 1995. The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolelis, M., Ghazanfar, A., Stambaugh, C., Oliveira, L., Laubach, M., Chapin, J., Nelson, R. and Kaas, J. 1998. Simultaneous encoding of tactile information by three primate cortical areas. Nature Neuroscience 1(7): 621–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Donovan-Anderson, M. 1997. Content and Comportment: On Embodiment and the Epistemic Availability of the World. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Shaugnessy, B. 1980. The Will: A Dual Aspect Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlis, D. 1997. Consciousness as self-function. Journal of Consciousness Studies 4(5/6): 509–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlis, D. 2000. The role(s) of belief in AI. In: J. Minker (ed), Logic-based AI: Proceedings of The Workshop on Logic-Based Artificial Intelligence. Chapter 14.

  • Perry, J. 1977. The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs 13: 3–21. Reprinted in A. Brook and R. DeVidi Self-reference and Self-awareness, pp. 143–159. Amsterdam: John Benjamin Publishers, 2001.

  • Perry, J. 1990. Self-notions. Logos 1990: 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. 1993. The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. 1995. Rip van Winkle and other characters. The European Review of Analytical Philosophy. 2: 13–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. 1998. Myself and “I”. In: M. Stamm (ed), Philosophie in Synthetischer Absicht, pp. 83–103. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 1994. The Language Instinct. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, G. and Anderson, M. L. 2004. A brief introduction to the guidance theory of representation. Proceedings of the 26th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. http://www.cogsci.northwestern.edu/cogsci2004/papers/paper122.pdf.

  • Rosenberg, G. and Anderson, M. L. (forthcoming). Content and action: The guidance theory of representation. http://www.cs.umd.edu/~anderson/papers/CNA.pdf.

  • Scholl, B. J. and Leslie, A. M. 1999. Modularity, development and ‘theory of mind’. Mind and Language 14(1): 131–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. 2001. The constructed and the secret self. In: A. Brook and R. DeVidi (eds), Self-reference and Self-awareness, pp. 247–268. John Benjamins Publishing Company.

  • Shoemaker, S. 1968. Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65: 555–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. 1990. Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science 14: 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. 1979. Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In: M. Bullowa (ed), Before Speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael L. Anderson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Anderson, M.L., Perlis, D.R. The roots of self-awareness. Phenom Cogn Sci 4, 297–333 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-4068-0

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-4068-0

Key Words

Navigation