Skip to main content
Log in

“Cognition” and Dynamical Cognitive Science

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Several philosophers have expressed concerns with some recent uses of the term ‘cognition’. Underlying a number of these concerns are claims that cognition is only located in the brain and that no compelling case has been made to use ‘cognition’ in any way other than as a cause of behavior that is representational in nature. These concerns center on two primary misapprehensions: First, that some adherents of dynamical cognitive science (DCS) think DCS implies the thesis of extended cognition and the rejection of representation, and second, that cognition is mistakenly equated with behavior. We make three points in response to these claims: First, there is no thoroughly entrenched conception of cognition as distinct from behavior that is being illegitimately disregarded. Second, we present Shapiro’s (Minds Mach 23: 353–375, 2013) exposition of dynamical systems theory as revealing a misunderstanding of the way that dynamical models are used in explanations of cognition and related phenomena. Accordingly, a proper conception of DCS’s methods facilitates an appreciation of extended cognition as a legitimate phenomenon of scientific investigation. Finally, we demonstrate that practicing cognitive scientists and psychologists are far more pluralistic in the phenomena they apply ‘cognition’ to than is suggested by some. At the heart of our disagreement with these concerned folks is that although we think it likely that some cognitive phenomena are representational, non-extended, and only in-between the ears, we also think there are good conceptual and empirical reasons to believe that many cognitive phenomena are non-representational, extended, and not confined to the brain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We wish to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for pushing us to make clearer the pluralism at the heart of our paper.

  2. We thank one of the anonymous reviewers for pressing the point that Shapiro (2013) is not defending a specific definition of ‘cognition’ so much as he is critiquing those like Chemero who, he believes, incorrectly equate cognition and behavior.

  3. Chemero is not alone in emphasizing intelligent behavior as a primary explanandum of cognitive science. Perhaps unlikely allies on this point, Thagard too claims “intelligent behavior” to be a primary target of explanation in cognition science (e.g., Thagard 2005, p. 19, 56, 74, 91, 107, 142).

  4. This typo is in the original article.

  5. Note that 1/f signaling is a more stringent requirement than mere functional equivalence. Otto and his notebook (Clark and Chalmers 1998) would likely not demonstrate 1/f signaling in the way that Inga’s neural networks would, though that is a question best arbitrated empirically.

References

  • Abrahamsen, A., & Bechtel, W. (2012). History and core themes. In K. Frankish & W. M. Ramsey (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of cognitive science (pp. 9–28). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2015). What is this cognition that is supposed to be embodied? Philosophical Psychology, 28, 755–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. (2009). What mindedness is. Europe’s Journal of Psychology, 4, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L., Richardson, M. J., & Chemero, A. (2012). Eroding the boundaries of cognition: Implications of embodiment. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4, 717–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2012). Why behaviorism isn’t Satanism. In J. Vonk & T. Shackelford (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of comparative evolutionary psychology (pp. 17–38). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. (2003). The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved model agent. Adaptive Behavior, 11, 209–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D., & Williams, P. L. (2015). Information processing and dynamics in minimally cognitive agents. Cognitive Science, 39, 1–38. doi:10.1111/cogs.12142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1990). Elephants don’t play chess. Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 6, 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buck, J. (1988). Synchronous rhythmic flashing of fireflies. II. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 63, 265–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaney, D. W. (2013). An overview of the first use of the terms cognition and behavior. Behavioral Sciences, 3, 143–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2003). Radical empiricism through the ages. Contemporary Psychology: APA Review of Books, 48, 18–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). Defending extended cognition. In B. Love, K. McRae, & V. Sloutsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th annual meeting of the cognitive science society (pp. 129–134). Austin: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). Review: Verbal behavior by B.F. Skinner. Language, 35, 26–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cromwell, H. C., & Panksepp, J. (2011). Rethinking the cognitive revolution from a neural perspective: How overuse/misuse of the term ‘cognition’ and the neglect of affective controls in behavioral neuroscience could be delaying progress in understanding the BrainMind. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 35, 2026–2035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ding, M., Chen, Y., & Kelso, J. A. S. (2002). Statistical analysis of timing errors. Brain and Cognition, 48, 98–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dotov, D. G., Nie, L., & Chemero, A. (2010). A demonstration of the transition from ready-to-hand to unready-to-hand. PLoS ONE, 5, e9433. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0009433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C. (2012). The complex systems approach: Rhetoric or revolution. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4, 72–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, A. K., Maye, A., Kurthen, M., & König, P. (2015). Where’s the action? The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 202–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Favela, L. H., & Chemero, A. (2015). Preliminary evidence for extended cognitive systems. Paper presented at the 106th Annual Meeting of the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, New Orleans.

  • Favela, L. H., & Chemero, A. (2016). The animal-environment system. In Y. Coelllo & M. H. Fischer (Eds.), Foundations of embodied cognition (Vol. 1, pp. 59–74)., Perceptual and emotional embodiment New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. London: Thomas Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2009). Where is my mind? London Review of Books, 31, 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J. (2006). Origin, structure, and role of background EEG activity. Part 4. Neural frame simulation. Clinical Neurophysiology, 117, 572–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, A. (2012). Cognitive science and cognitive sciences. Journal of Cognitive Science, 13, 471–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haken, H., Kelso, J. A. S., & Bunz, H. (1985). A theoretical model of phase transitions in human hand movements. Biological Cybernetics, 51, 347–356.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, S. J., & Richardson, M. J. (2009). Horsing around: Spontaneous four-legged coordination. Journal of Motor Behavior, 41, 519–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (1988). Representation and content in some (actual) theories of perception. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 19, 175–214. (as reprinted in Hatfield 2009, pp. 50–87).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (2000). The brain’s “new” science: Psychology, neurophysiology, and constraint. Philosophy of Science, 67, S388–S403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (2009). Perception and cognition: Essays in the philosophy of psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausdorff, J. M., Peng, C. K., Ladin, Z., Wei, J. Y., & Goldberger, A. L. (1995). Is walking a random walk? Evidence for long-range correlations in stride interval of human gait. Journal of Applied Physiology, 78, 349–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hergenhahn, B. R. (2008). An introduction to the history of psychology (6th ed.). Belmont: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holden, J. G. (2005). Gauging the fractal dimension of response times from cognitive tasks. In M. A. Riley & G. C. Van Orden (Eds.), Tutorials in Contemporary Nonlinear Methods for Behavioral Sciences (pp. 267–318). Retrieved March 10, 2012 from http://www.nsf.gov/sbe/bcs/pac/nmbs/nmbs.jsp.

  • Huffman, C. (2013). Alcmaeon. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). Retrieved September 6, 2014 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/alcmaeon/.

  • Ihlen, E. A. F. (2012). Introduction to multifractal detrended fluctuation analysis in Matlab. Frontiers in Physiology, 3, 141. doi:10.3389/fphys.2012.00141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihlen, E. A. F., & Vereijken, B. (2010). Interaction-dominant dynamics in human cognition: Beyond 1/f a fluctuation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 139, 436–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1885). On the function of cognition. Mind, 10, 27–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S., Saltzman, E. L., & Tuller, B. (1986). The dynamical perspective on speech production: Data and theory. Journal of Phonetics, 14, 29–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayville, J. M., Jantzen, K. J., Fuchs, A., Steinberg, F. L., & Kelso, J. A. S. (2002). Cortical and subcortical networks underlying syncopated and synchronized coordination revealed using fMRI. Human Brain Mapping, 17, 214–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClintock, M. K. (1971). Menstrual synchrony and suppression. Nature, 229, 244–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peng, C. K., Havlin, S., Hausdorff, J. M., Mietus, J. E., Stanley, H. E., & Goldberger, A. L. (1995). Fractal mechanisms and heart rate dynamics: Long-range correlations and their breakdown with disease. Journal of Electrocardiology, 28, 59–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2000). Consciousness. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 23, 557–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2011). Embodied cognition. New York: Routledge.

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2013). Dynamics and cognition. Minds and Machines, 23, 353–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2012). Complexity and extended phenomenological-cognitive systems. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4, 35–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M. (2007). The continuity of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadnitski, T. (2012). Measuring fractality. Frontiers in Physiology, 3, 127. doi:10.3389/fphys.2012.00127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen, D. G., & Dixon, J. A. (2009). The self-organization of insight: Entropy and power laws in problem solving. The Journal of Problem Solving, 2, 72–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2005). Mind: Introduction to cognitive science (2nd ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of the mind. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Orden, G. C., Holden, J. G., & Turvey, M. T. (2005). Human cognition and 1/f scaling. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 134, 117–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, M. M. J. W., Favela, L. H., Malone, M. L., & Richardson, M. J. (2013). Modeling the dynamics of risky choice. Ecological Psychology, 25, 293–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Rooij, M., & Van Orden, G. (2011). It’s about space, it’s about time, neuroeconomics and the brain sublime. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 25, 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenmakers, E. J., Farrell, S., & Ratcliff, R. (2005). Human cognition and a pile of sand: A discussion on serial correlations and self-organized criticality. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 134, 108–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, L. M., & Greenwood, P. E. (2007). 1/f noise. Scholarpedia, 2(12), 1537. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.1537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, R., & Ward, R. (2009). Representation in dynamical agents. Neural Networks, 22, 258–266.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Watrin, J. P., & Darwich, R. (2012). On behaviorism in the cognitive revolution: Myth and reactions. Review of General Psychology, 16, 269–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winfree, A. T. (1967). Biological rhythms and the behavior of populations of coupled oscillators. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 16, 15–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to first thank the current Editor in Chief of Minds and Machines, Mariarosaria Taddeo, and former Editor in Chief, Gregory Wheeler, for their support of this project at various points of the submission and review process. We also thank two anonymous reviewers for their very detailed, thorough, and helpful comments. We are very grateful to Tony Chemero for helpful discussions and detailed comments on previous versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis H. Favela.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Favela, L.H., Martin, J. “Cognition” and Dynamical Cognitive Science. Minds & Machines 27, 331–355 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-016-9411-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-016-9411-4

Keywords

Navigation