Skip to main content
Log in

Free Choice Impossibility Results

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Free Choice is the principle that possibly p or q implies and is implied by possibly p and possibly q. A variety of recent attempts to validate Free Choice rely on a nonclassical semantics for disjunction, where the meaning of p or q is not a set of possible worlds. This paper begins with a battery of impossibility results, showing that some kind of nonclassical semantics for disjunction is required in order to validate Free Choice. The paper then provides a positive account of Free Choice, by identifying a family of dynamic semantics for disjunction that can validate the inference. On all such theories, the meaning of p or q has two parts. First, p or q requires that our information is consistent with each of p and q. Second, p or q narrows down our information by eliminating some worlds. It turns out that this second component of or is well behaved: there is a strongest such meaning that p or q can express, consistent with validating Free Choice. The strongest such meaning is the classical one, on which p or q eliminates any world where both p and q are false. In this way, the classical meaning of disjunction turns out to be intimately related to the validity of Free Choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Aloni, M. (2007). Free choice, modals, and imperatives. Natural Language Semantics, 15(1), 65–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Alonso-Ovalle, L. (2006). Disjunction in alternative semantics. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts Amherst.

  3. Bacon, A. (2015). Stalnaker’s thesis in context. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 8(1), 131–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Barker, C. (2010). Free choice permission as resource-sensitive reasoning. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3(10), 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Charlow, N. (2015). Triviality for restrictor conditionals. Noûs.

  6. Chemla, E., & Bott, L. (2014). Processing inferences at the semantics/pragmatics frontier: disjunction and free choice. Cognition, 130(3), 380–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Fox, D. (2007). Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. In Sauerland, U., & Stateva, P. (Eds.) Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics (pp. 71–120). Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, MIT.

  8. Franke, M. (2011). Quantity implicatures, exhaustive interpretation, and rational conversation. Semantics and Pragmatics, 4(1), 1–82.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Fusco, M. (2015). Deontic modals and the semantics of choice. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(28), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Geurts, B. (2005). Entertaining alternatives: disjunctions as modals. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1990). Dynamic montague grammar. In Kalman, L., & Polos, L. (Eds.) Papers from the second symposium on logic and language (pp. 3–48). Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.

  12. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(1), 39–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991). Two theories of dynamic semantics. In van Eijck, J. (Ed.) Lecture notes in computer science, (Vol. 478 pp. 55–64): Springer.

  14. Hacquard, V. (2010). On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Nat. Lang. Semantics, 18, 79–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Hájek, A. (2013). Staying regular?.

  16. Hamblin, C.L. (1973). Questions in montague english. In Foundations of language (Vol. 10, pp. 41–53).

  17. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst MA.

  18. Heim, I. (1983). On the projection problem for presuppositions. WCCFL, 2, 114–125.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9(3), 183–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Kamp, H. (1974). Free choice permission. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society (pp. 57–74).

  21. Karttunen, L. (1972). Possible and must. In Kimball, J. (Ed.) Syntax and semantics, (Vol. 1 pp. 1–20): New York Academic Press.

  22. Karttunen, L. (1974). Presuppositions and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics, 1, 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Klinedinst, N. (2007). Plurality and possibility. PhD thesis, UCLA.

  24. Kratzer, A. (1986). Conditionals. Chicago Linguistics Society, 22, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In von Stechow, A., & Wunderlich, D. (Eds.) Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–650): de Gruyter.

  26. Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kratzer, A., & Shimoyama, J. (2002). Indeterminate pronouns: The view from japanese. In Otsu, Y. (Ed.) The proceedings of the third Tokyo conference on psycholinguistics. Tokyo: Hituzi Syobo.

  28. Lassiter, D. (2016). Must, knowledge, and (in)directness. Natural Language Semantics, 24(2), 117–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review, 85, 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Miller, Z. (2016). The reformulation argument: reining in gricean pragmatics. Philosophical Studies, 173(2), 525–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Moss, S. (2015). On the semantics and pragmatics of epistemic modals. Semantics and Pragmatics.

  32. Romoli, J., & Santorio, P. (2017). Probability and implicatures: a unified account of the scalar effects of disjunction under modals. Semantics and Pragmatics.

  33. Rothschild, D. (2012). Expressing credences. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112(1), 99–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Rothschild, D., & Yalcin, S. (2015). On the dynamics of conversation. Nous.

  35. Russell, J., & Hawthorne, J. (2016). General dynamic triviality theorems. Philosophical Review, 125(3), 307–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Schulz, K. (2005). A pragmatic solution for the paradox of free choice permission. Synthese, 147(2), 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Simons, M. (2005). Dividing things up: the semantics of or and the modal/or interaction. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 271–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Starr, W.B. (2016). Expressing permission. In Proceedings of SALT, Vol. 26. Ithaca: CLC Publications.

  40. Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(4), 487–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Strawson, P.F. (1952). Introduction to logical theory. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Swanson, E. (2011). How not to theorize about the language of subjective uncertainty. In Egan, A., & Weatherson, B. (Eds.) Epistemic modality: Oxford University Press.

  43. Swanson, E. (2012). The application of constraint semantics to the language of subjective uncertainty. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1–28.

  44. Tieu, L., Romoli, J., Zhou, P., Crain, S. (2016). Children’s knowledge of free choice inferences and scalar implicatures. Journal of Semantics, 33(2), 269–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. van Benthem, J. (1996). Exploring logical dynamics. CSLI Publications.

  46. Veltman, F. (1985). Logics for conditionals. PhD thesis. University of Amsterdam.

  47. Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(3), 221–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. von Fintel, K. (1997). Bare plurals, bare conditionals, and only. Journal of Semantics, 14, 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. von Fintel, K. (1999). Npi-licensing, strawson-entailment, and context-dependency. Journal of Semantics, 16(1).

  50. von Fintel, K. (2001). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context.

  51. von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A.S. (2010). Must stay strong!. Natural Language Semantics, 18(4), 351–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. von Wright, G.He. (1968). Deontic logic and the theory of conditions. Critica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofia, 2(6), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Willer, M. (2015). Simplifying counterfactuals. In Proceedings of the 20th Amsterdam colloquium (pp. 428–437).

  54. Willer, M. (2018). Two puzzles about agentive. Central APA: Can.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116(464), 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Yalcin, S. (2012). Bayesian expressivism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112(2), 123–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Yalcin, S. (2015). Epistemic modality. De Re. Ergo, 2(19).

  58. Zimmermann, T.E. (2000). Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics, 8, 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was supported by Research Grants Council Grant #23602118.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simon Goldstein.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Definition 7

If a set of possibility operators is partitionable and all satisfy Free Choice, then disjunction is not propositional.

  1. 1.

    {wwRw},{vvRv}, and {uuRu} are not empty.

  2. 2.

    {wwRw} = {vvRv}∪{uuRu}

  3. 3.

    {vvRv}∩{uuRu} =

  4. 4.

    ∃A,B ∈L : A = {vvRv} & B = {uuRu}.

Fact 1

If a set of possibility operators is partitionable and all satisfy Free Choice, then disjunction is not propositional.

Proof

Suppose ♢A, ♢B, and ♢C are partitionable and satisfy Free Choice. Let B and C denote {vwRBv}, and {vwRCv} respectively, where A = BC. Suppose disjunction is propositional, with ∗ as the witnessing operator. Let A and B be true at exactly B and C respectively. Then by the validity of Free Choice for ♢A, ♢A(A ∨B) is true at w just in case ♢AA and ♢AB are true at w. A ∨B = BC. So BC is consistent with BC just in case B is consistent with BC and C is consistent with BC. However, we also know that BC is inconsistent with C if B is inconsistent with C, since ♢C(A ∨B) is true at w only if ♢CA is true at w. Since B is inconsistent with C, it follows that BC is inconsistent with C. Similarly, we know that BC is inconsistent with B if C is inconsistent with B, since ♢B(A ∨B) is true at w only if ♢BB is true at w. Since C is inconsistent with B, it follows that BC is inconsistent with B. But if BC is inconsistent with both B and with C, then BC is inconsistent with BC. Contradiction. □

Fact 2

If any conditional possibility operator ♢i(⋅)(⋅) satisfies Conditional Free Choice, then ∨ is not propositional.

Proof

Let ♢(⋅)(⋅) be the witnessing operator with accessibility relation R. Now take some arbitrary world w such that ♢(⋅)(⋅) has a non-trivial accessibility relation at that world, such that there are at least two worlds v and u where wRv and wRu. Now I will assume that there are two propositions A and B that partition {vwRv}, and are the semantic value of some sentences A and B. Now let ⊤ be a claim true at every possible world. By Conditional Free Choice, w♢(⊤)(A ∨B) just in case w♢(⊤)(A) and w♢(⊤)(B). In this semantic framework, the last condition in turn requires that ∃v : wRv & vAB iff ∃v : wRv & vA and ∃v : wRv & vB. By the construction of R, we know that this condition is satisfied. But now consider the conditionals ♢(A)(A ∨B) and ♢(B)(A ∨B). If ♢ satisfies Conditional Free Choice, then we know that w♢(A)(A ∨B) only if w♢(A)(B). This in turn implies that ∃v : wRv & vA & vAB only if ∃v : wRv & vA & vB. But there is no such v in both A and B, since these propositions are inconsistent. So there is no accessible v where both A and AB hold. Likewise, w♢(B)(A ∨B) only if w♢(B)(A); which in turn implies that ∃v : wRv & vB & vAB only if ∃v : wRv & vA & vB. Since this last condition cannot obtain, we know that there is no accessible v where both B and AB. But every accessible v world is either an A or a B world. So AB can’t hold at any accessible world in the first place. □

Definition 10 (Credal Free Choice)

There is some operator ∗ such that for any rational Pr,A,B:

Pr(AB) > 0 iff Pr(A) > 0 and Pr(B) > 0.

Fact 3

If Credal Free Choice holds, then Pr(A) = 0 or Pr(A) = 1 for every rational Pr,A.

Proof

Pr(A∗(WA)) = Pr(A∗(WA))×Pr(A∗(WA)∣A)+Pr(WAPr(A∗(WA)∣WA). Pr(AA) = 1, which means Pr(WAA) = 0, which implies Pr(A ∗ (WA)∣A) = 0 by Credal Free Choice. By similar reasoning, Pr(A ∗ (WA)∣WA) = 0. So Pr(A ∗ (WA)) = 0. So by Credal Free Choice again, Pr(A) = 0 or Pr(WA) = 0. So Pr(A) is 0 or 1. □

Fact 4

If Free Choice is valid, then A ∨B is not distributive for arbitrary atomic A and B.

Proof

Consider some arbitrary atomic p and β. Let s be some context which contains some p worlds, some β worlds, and no worlds where both p and β are false. Since s[p]≠ and s[β]≠, we know by Dynamic Free Choice that s[p ∨ β]≠. Now let s¬p be {wsw(p) = 0}, and let s¬β be {wsw(β) = 0}. By Dynamic Free Choice, s¬p[p ∨ β] = , since s¬p[p] = . Similarly, s¬β[p ∨ β] = . Now suppose p ∨ β is distributive. Then for any ws¬p, {w}[p ∨ β] = . Similarly, for any ws¬β, {w}[p ∨ β] = . But s = s¬ps¬β. So for any ws, {w}[p ∨ β] = . So, supposing p ∨ β is distributive, s[p ∨ β] = . This is inconsistent; so p ∨ β is not distributive. □

Fact 5

Suppose that entailment is transitive, that ♢ is upwards monotonic, that the T axiom is valid, and that the 4 axiom is valid. Then FC I is valid iff Disjunction-Possibility Link is valid.

Proof

By the T axiom, A ∨B implies ♢(A ∨B). By Free Choice, this last implies ♢A ∧♢B. So by the transitivity of entailment A ∨B implies ♢A ∧♢B. Now suppose A ∨B⊧♢A. Then ♢(A ∨B)⊧♢♢A by upwards monotonicity, which by the 4 axiom implies ♢A. □

Definition 16

s[A ∨tB] = s[♢A][♢B]

Fact 6

If ∗ validates Free Choice, then ∗ is at least as strong as ∨t.

Proof

By the T axiom for ♢, . Suppose FC 1 is valid for ∗; then and . This is sufficient to show that , and hence that

Definition 18

∗ is factorizable iff there is some distributive operator ⋈ such that [A ∗B] = s[A⋈B][A ∨tB].

Definition 19

s[A ∨uB] = s[A] ∪ s[B]

Definition 20

s[A ∨utB] = s[A ∨uB][A ∨tB].

Fact 7

if ∗ is factorizable and satisfies Free Choice, and if A⊮B and B⊮A, then .

Proof

Suppose that s[A ∨uB][A ∨tB] = s. We must show that s⊧A ∗B. We can suppose that s is not , since the proof would be trivial in that case. Since s[A ∨uB][A ∨tB] = s, we know that (i) s[A]≠ and s[B]≠, and (ii) s is made up exclusively of worlds w where either {w}⊧A or {w}⊧B. From (i), we know that the possibility tests required by ∗ are satisfied. To complete our proof, we can use (ii) to show that s[A⋈B] = s.

Since ⋈ is distributive, we know that s[A⋈B] = {ws∣{w}⊧A⋈B}. So to prove that s[A⋈B] = s, we can take an arbitrary ws and show that {w}⊧A⋈B. From (ii) we know that either {w}⊧A or {w}⊧B. We can show that in either case {w}⊧A⋈B.

So suppose the former. Either {w}⊧B or not. Suppose the former. Then since {w}⊧A and {w}⊧B, we have that {w}⊧♢A and {w}⊧♢B. So since ∗ satisfies Free Choice, we know that {w}⊧♢(A ∗B). Since {w} is maximal, this means that {w}⊧A ∗B and hence {w}⊧A⋈B.

But now suppose instead that {w}⊧A and {w}⊮B. Now let v be such that {v}⊧B and {v}⊮A. Here, we rely on the assumption that A and B are not ordered by strength. First, this means that {w,v}⊧♢A and {w,v}⊧♢B. So by Free Choice {w,v}⊧♢(A ∗B). But this means that {w,v}[A⋈B]≠. This in turn implies that {w,v}[A⋈B] = {w,v}. For otherwise one of w or v would be removed, in which case one of ♢A or ♢B would not be supported by {w,v}[A⋈B], and so {w,v}⊮♢(A ∗B). So since {w,v}⊧A⋈B and ⋈ is distributive, {w}⊧A⋈B. □

Definition 23

∗ is quasi-conjunctive relative to R iff for any A and B, if A and B are expressible via R, then AB = AB.

Fact 8

If Wide Free Choice is valid for ♢i and disjunction is propositional, then disjunction is quasi-conjunctive relative to Ri.

Proof

Suppose Wide Free Choice is valid for ♢i and disjunction is propositional, expressing the operation ∗. Now suppose that A and B are expressible via Ri. That is, suppose iA = A and suppose iB = B, for some A and B. By Wide Free Choice, ♢iA ∨♢iB implies each of ♢iA and ♢iB, and vice versa. But this means that i A ∨♢i B = iAiB. Since i A ∨♢i B = AB, this means that AB = AB. □

Fact 9

Wide Free Choice is valid for ♢i and ∨t iff for any w,v,u: if wRiv then uRiv.

Proof

Suppose Wide Free Choice is valid for ♢i and ∨t. Then whenever s⊧♢♢iA and s⊧♢♢iB, we have that s⊧♢iA and s⊧♢iB. This means that if there is some ws where wRiv and vA, we are guaranteed that for every ws there is an accessible v world where A. This means that if wRiv, then uRiv for any u. Otherwise, s could contain just w and u, and then {v} would be a counterexampling choice of A. Conversely, suppose that for any w,v,u: if wRiv then uRiv. Now suppose s⊧♢♢iA and s⊧♢♢iB. Then ∃ws : {vwRiv}[A]≠. Now let u be an arbitrary world in s. By the constraint above, we know that {vuRiv}[A]≠, since {vwRiv} = {vuRiv}. So s⊧♢iA. □

Fact 10

Free Choice, Dual Prohibition, Contraposition, and Transitivity imply Explosion.

Proof

By Free Choice, . So by Contraposition . By Dual Prohibition, . So by Transitivity, and hence by Contraposition again . □

Fact 11

If Free Choice and Dual Prohibition are valid, then Explosion is valid.

Proof

Suppose s⊧♢A. Suppose that s is non-empty (otherwise the proof is trivial). We can now show that s⊧♢B. First, s[A]≠. Since Dual Prohibition is valid, this means that s[A ∨B]≠. But since Free Choice is valid, this last implies that s[B]≠. So s⊧♢B. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldstein, S. Free Choice Impossibility Results. J Philos Logic 49, 249–282 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09517-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09517-9

Keywords

Navigation