Skip to main content
Log in

A Defense of the Objective/Subjective Moral Ought Distinction

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I motivate and defend the distinction between an objective and a subjective moral sense of “ought.” I begin by looking at the standard way the distinction is motivated, namely by appealing to relatively simple cases where an agent does something she thinks is best, but her action has a tragic outcome. I argue that these cases fail to do the job—the intuitions they elicit can be explained without having to distinguish between different senses of “ought.” However, these cases are on the right track—I argue that more sophisticated versions of the cases provide strong motivation for the distinction. I then discuss two important problems for the distinction: the “which ‘ought’ is more important?” problem, and the “annoying profusion of ‘oughts’” problem. I argue that each of these problems can be solved in several different ways.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This distinction is stressed by Ross (1930, 1939).

  2. See, e.g., Ewing (1948: 112–47), Brandt (1959: 360–67), Russell (1966), Feldman (1986, 2012), Portmore (2011), and Dorsey (2012). I cite several additional examples in the next section.

  3. From now on, unless otherwise noted, when I use the term “ought,” I will always have the overall moral sense in mind.

  4. See, e.g., Pollock (1979: 109–10), Gibbard (2005: 340), and Parfit (2011: 151–52).

  5. Objectivists include Moore ([1903] 1993, [1912] 2005), Ross (1930), Thomson (1986), Zimmerman (1996), and Graham (2010). Subjectivists include Prichard ([1932] 2002), Ross (1939), Howard-Snyder (2005), Zimmerman (2006, 2008), and Mason (2013). Another option: one might hold that “ought” is univocal (in its overall moral sense) and context sensitive (see Kolodny and MacFarlane 2010). I will set this view aside in this paper.

  6. My talk here of the “objective ought” and the “subjective ought” is shorthand for the “objective sense of ‘ought’” and the “subjective sense of ‘ought,’” respectively. For ease of exposition, I will often use shorthand like this in what follows.

  7. Portmore (2005) appeals to this type of value.

  8. Schroeder (2007) expresses similar puzzlement.

  9. Regan (1980: 264–65), Ross (2006: 174), and Parfit (2011: 159–60) develop similar cases. Note that the Dr. Jill case is importantly different from the cases I have discussed so far. All of the cases discussed up to this point feature protagonists who have misleading or false information. However, Dr. Jill doesn’t have misleading information or any false beliefs. Instead, she has incomplete information—she doesn’t know which drug is the killer and which is the cure. In Sect. 5.2, we will see how incomplete-information cases might be thought to pose their own special problem for Sense-Splitters by forcing them to adopt an annoying profusion of oughts.

  10. See, esp., Zimmerman (2008: chap. 1, 2014: chap. 4).

  11. See, e.g., Ross (1939: 147) and Zimmerman (2008: 7).

  12. See, e.g., Feldman (2000), Copp (1997), and Baker (Forthcoming).

  13. See, e.g., McLeod (2001), Feldman (1986), Darwall (1997), and Chang (2004).

  14. See, e.g., Portmore (2008).

  15. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this line of thought to me.

  16. See, esp., Zimmerman (2008: sect. 3.5, 2014: chap. 1). For a contrasting view, see Hedden (2012).

  17. See, e.g., Wedgewood (2007: 118, 2016: 147).

  18. Cf. Kolodny and MacFarlane (2010: 121).

  19. I have modified this case slightly for my purposes.

  20. Cf. Kiesewetter (2011) and Zimmerman (2014: 82–87).

  21. Thanks to an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this case. Note that while this case can be used to pose a problem for Sense-Splitting, that is not why Schroeder discusses it. He discusses it because he wants to defend the idea that oughts are determined by the balance of reasons, and he thinks that Four Envelopes poses a potential problem for such a view. Schroeder ultimately argues that the problem can be solved by embracing a certain type of expressivism about epistemic expressions.

  22. I have been assuming that Xiao has moral duties to herself, an assumption that can be challenged [see, e.g., Ross (1939)]. If Xiao has no moral duties to herself, then she is arguably morally permitted to choose any of the four envelopes. We can, however, remove this complication by making Xiao’s choices other-directed; for instance, we can stipulate that the money in the chosen envelope will go to charity. My conclusions about the case remain unchanged with this added stipulation.

References

  • Baker, Derek. Forthcoming. Skepticism About Ought Simpliciter. In Oxford Studies of Metaethics, 13th edition, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Brandt, Richard B. 1959. Ethical Theory: The Problems of Normative and Critical Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Ruth. 2004. All Things Considered. Philosophical Perspectives 18: 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, David. 1997. The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason. Social Philosophy and Policy 14: 86–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen. 1997. Learning from Frankena: A Philosophical Remembrance. Ethics 107: 685–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorsey, Dale. 2012. Objective Morality, Subjective Morality and the Explanatory Question. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 6(3): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewing, A. C. 1948. The Definition of Good. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Fred. 1986. Doing the Best We Can: An Essay in Informal Deontic Logic. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Fred. 2012. True and Useful: On the Structure of a Two Level Normative Theory. Utilitas 24: 151–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Richard. 2000. The Ethics of Belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60: 667–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, Allan. 2005. Truth and Correct Belief. Philosophical Issues 15: 338–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, Peter A. 2010. In Defense of Objectivism about Moral Obligation. Ethics 121: 88–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedden, Brian. 2012. Options and the Subjective Ought. Philosophical Studies 158: 343–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, Frances. 2005. It’s the Thought that Counts. Utilitas 17: 265–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Frank. 1986. A Probabilistic Approach to Moral Responsibility. In Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science VII, ed. Ruth Barcan Marcus, Georg J. W. Dorn, and Paul Weingartner, 351–365. North Holland: Elsevier Science Publishers.

  • Jackson, Frank. 1991. Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection. Ethics 101: 461–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiesewetter, Benjamin. 2011. ‘Ought’ and the Perspective of the Agent. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 5(3): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, Niko, and John MacFarlane. 2010. Ifs and Oughts. Journal of Philosophy 107: 115–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2002. The Notional Category of Modality. In Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings, ed. Paul Portner, and Barbara H. Partee, 289–323. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, Elinor. 2013. Objectivism and Prospectivism About Rightness. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7(2): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, Owen. 2001. Just Plain “Ought”. The Journal of Ethics 5: 269–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903) 1993. Principia Ethica, Rev. edition. Ed. Thomas Baldwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Moore, G. E. (1912) 2005. Ethics, Ed. W. H. Shaw. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Oddie, Graham, and Peter Menzies. 1992. An Objectivist’s Guide to Subjective Value. Ethics 102: 512–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters. Vol. 1. Ed. Samuel Scheffler. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Pollock, John. 1979. A Plethora of Epistemological Theories. In Knowledge and Justification, ed. G. S. Pappas, 93–113. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore, Douglas W. 2005. Combining Teleological Ethics with Evaluator Relativism: A Promising Result. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86: 95–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore, Douglas W. 2008. Are Moral Reasons Morally Overriding? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11: 369–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore, Douglas W. 2011. Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, H. A. (1932) 2002. Duty and Ignorance of Fact. In Moral Writings, ed Jim MacAdam, 85–110. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Regan, Donald. 1980. Utilitarianism and Co-Operation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Jacob. 2006. Acceptance and Practical Reason. Ph.D. Thesis, Rutgers University.

  • Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. 1939. The Foundations of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1966. The Elements of Ethics. In Philosophical Essays, 13–59. New York: Simon and Schuster.

  • Schroeder, Mark. 2007. Teleology, Agent-Relative Value, and ‘Good’. Ethics 117: 265–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, Mark. Forthcoming. Getting Perspective on Objective Reasons. Ethics.

  • Smith, Holly M. 2010. Subjective Rightness. Social Philosophy and Policy 27: 64–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1986. Imposing Risks. In Rights, Restitution, and Risks, ed. William Parent, 173–191. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgewood, Ralph. 2007. The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgewood, Ralph. 2016. Objective and Subjective ‘Ought’. In Deontic Modality, ed. Nate Charlow, and Matthew Chrisman, 142–168. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael J. 1996. The Concept of Moral Obligation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael J. 2006. Is Moral Obligation Objective or Subjective? Utilitas 18: 329–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael J. 2008. Living with Uncertainty: The Moral Significance of Ignorance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael J. 2014. Ignorance and Moral Obligation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many people gave me valuable feedback on drafts of this paper. Thanks especially to Fred Feldman, Luis Oliveira, Scott Hill, and an anonymous referee for this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristian Olsen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Olsen, K. A Defense of the Objective/Subjective Moral Ought Distinction. J Ethics 21, 351–373 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-017-9258-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-017-9258-9

Keywords

Navigation