Skip to main content
Log in

Motivating a Pragmatic Approach to Naturalized Social Ontology

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent contributions to the philosophy of the social sciences have motivated ontological commitments using appeals to the social sciences (naturalized social ontologies). These arguments rely on social scientific realism about the social sciences, the view that our social scientific theories are approximately true. I apply a distinction formulated in metaontology between ontologically loaded and unloaded meanings of existential quantification to argue that there is a pragmatic approach to naturalized social ontology that is minimally realist (it treats existence claims as true or false) but that is ontologically austere. I argue that the extant arguments may be construed in terms of this pragmatic approach. The result is an approach to social ontology that is deflationist about naturalized social ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The degree of empirical success in the social sciences and its implications for the ontology and scientific status of the social sciences has been a large point of contention. See Elster (2009), Epstein (2015), Guala (2007), Hawley (2018), Kincaid (1996), Northcott (2015), Taagepera (2008) and Harp and Khalifa (2017).

  2. These entities are ontologically dubious because they depend on the minds of agents and so need not have existence unto themselves. This arises in the debate between methodological (and ontological) individualists and holists. See Zahle and Collin (2013) for an overview of the history of this debate as well as recent innovations.

  3. SSR assumes a definition of scientific realism as the thesis that our best scientific theories are true or approximately true. This differs from other approaches to the question about realism about social science and social ontology. For example, Guala (2016) and Ruben (2014), who are concerned with questions about the dependence of the social on the mental and Bunge (1993) who takes realism about social science to be the view that the social sciences can be objective. Moreover, it differs from the realism defined by Currie (1988), which is about the aims of science.

  4. Note that this argument stands in contrast to the one examined by Harp and Khalifa (2017), which emphasizes appeals to best explanations.

  5. Kincaid uses Chronbach and Meehl (1955). On their view, constructs are embedded in nomological nets—or collections of lawlike generalizations that describe the way in which the construct relates to other variables. Hence, Kincaid seems to focus on both converging evidence and causal explanation.

  6. The income inequality hypothesis posits social status structure as a cause of poor health among the poor. Levels of inequality are measured using the Gini Coefficient and epidemiologic data (stress, obesity, rates of diseases, etc.).

  7. The strict ‘unobservability’ of these entities might be contested—in economic theory, unobservability of preferences has been a point of contention. One might launch similar arguments here. See Hausman (1998).

  8. The data here are used to predict more data. Using old data, we should expect new data points to fit along a line predicted by the old data. There are difficult issues associated with novel prediction in these contexts that go beyond the purview of this paper. See Forster (2007) for a discussion of data and novel prediction.

  9. For example, Kris McDaniel’s chapter in Chalmers et al. (2009) invokes a Heidegerrian equivocalist, Tahko (2015) provides an overview of the discussion, particularly its connection to the Quine-Carnap debate. For treatments of these issues in touch with Carnap’s significance, see Blatti and Lapointe (2016).

  10. Even if there are multiple senses of ‘exist’ we might disagree about their relative importance. Equivocalists may give arguments for thinking that there is a privileged meaning of ‘exists’. Univocalists may instead argue that there is one sense of ‘exists’.

  11. I follow Psillos (1999).

  12. One could appeal to “acceptance” as discussed by van Fraassen. My proposal suggests a way of positing acceptance but enabling talk about the truth of scientific claims (by giving a deflated reading of their truth).

  13. Thomasson’s account prohibits defining the application conditions for F in terms of the existence of F. See Thomasson (2015, 96).

  14. These inferences might be understood in Bayesian terms.

  15. See Markus and Borsboom (2013) and Strauss and Smith (2009) for discussions of construct validation.

  16. See Kincaid (2018) for a defense of the reality of race along these lines.

  17. These are not biological realist attitudes, but constructionist ones. Constructionists argue that race is constructed but real. See Haslanger (2000).

  18. To clarify: the race assigned to an individual by a researcher or interviewer. Saperstein observed differences in reported incomes depending on which measure was used. See p. 65 Fig. 1.

  19. The pragmatic approach might generalize beyond the social and behavioral sciences to the natural sciences. However, there may be epistemic considerations that justify the traditional realist interpretation of existential claims about the natural sciences. Both the concerns over empirical success and ontological dubiousness mentioned at the beginning might press us to be more cautious in the case of the social sciences.

References

  • Ainsworth, D., and D. Downey. 1998. Assessing the Oppositional Culture Explanation for Racial/Ethnic Differences in School Performance. American Sociological Review 63: 536–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blatti, S., and S. Lapointe, eds. 2016. Ontology After Carnap. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Online Document Bricker, P. (Winter 2016) "Ontological Commitment" Retrieved: March 28th, 2021, from: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/ontological-commitment/.

  • Bryant, A. 2020. Keep the chickens cooped: The epistemic inadequacy of free range metaphysics. Synthese 197: 1867–1887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borsboom, D., Mellenbergh, G.J., & J. van Heerden. 2003a. Validity and truth. In New developments in psychometrics: Proceedings of the international psychometrics society, eds. H. Yanai, A. Okada, K. Shingemasu et al., 321–328. Tokyo: Springer.

  • Borsboom, D., G. Mellenbergh, and J. van Heerden. 2003b. The Theoretical Status of Latent Variables. Psychological Review 110: 203–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. 1993. Realism and Antirealism in Social Science. Theory and Decision 35: 207–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology. Revue Interationale de Philosophie, 4.

  • Chalmers, D., Manley, D. and R. Wasserman, eds. 2009. Metametaphysics: New Essays On The Foundations Of Ontology. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Chakravartty, A. 2017. Scientific Ontology: Integrating Naturalist Metaphysics and Voluntarist Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cronbach, L., and P. Meehl. 1955. Construct Validity in Psychological Tests. Psychological Bulletin 4 (52): 281–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. 1988. Realism in the Social Sciences: Social Kinds and Social Laws. In Relativism and Realism in Science, ed. R. Nola, 205–228. Norwell: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J., and A. Lewis. 2015. Despite Best Intentions: Why Racial Inequality Thrives in Good Schools. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, W. 2014. Who Rules America? Challenges to Corporate and Class Dominance, 6th ed. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. 2009. Reintroducting Prediction to Explanation. Philosophy of Science 76: 444–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. 2009. Excessive Ambitions. Capitalism and Society 4: 1.

  • Epstein, B. 2015. The Ant Trap. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. 2017. Social Ontology. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Social Science, eds. A. Rosenberg and L. McIntyre, 240–253. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. 2018. Social Ontology. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/social-ontology/.

  • Entwisle, D., K. Alexander, and L. Steffel Olson. 2005. First Grade and Educational Attainment by Age 22: A New Story. American Journal of Sociology 110: 1458–1502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forster, M. 2007. A Philosopher’s Guide to Empirical Success. Philosophy of Science 74: 588–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gradin, C. 2014. Race and Income Distribution: Evidence from the USA, Brazil and South Africa. Review of Development Economics 18: 73–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F. 2007. The Philosophy of Social Science: Metaphysical and Empirical. Philosophy Compass 2 (6): 954–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F. 2016. Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harp, R. and Khalifa, K. 2017. Realism and Anti-Realism. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Social Science, eds. A. Rosenberg and L. McIntyre, 254–269. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. 2000. Gender and Race: (What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Them To Be? Nous 34: 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. 1998. Problems with Realism and Economics. Economics and Philosophy 14: 185–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. 2018. Social Science as a Guide to Social Metaphysics? Journal of General Philosophy of Science 49: 187–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. 2009. Ambitious, Yet Modest, Metaphysics. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, eds. D. Chalmers, D. Manley and R. Wasserman, 260–289. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. 2016. Carnap’s Big Idea. In Ontology After Carnap, ed. S. Blatti and S. Lapointe, 13–30. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hood, B. 2013. Psychological Measurement and Methodological Realism. Erkenntnis 78: 739–761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 1996. The Philosophical Foundations of the Social Sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 2000. Global Arguments and Local Realism in the Social Sciences. Philosophy of Science 67: 667–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 2008. Structural Realism and the Social Sciences. Philosophy of Science 75: 720–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 2015. Debating the Reality of Social Classes. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46: 189–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 2018. Debating the Reality of Race, Caste and Ethnicity. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 48: 139–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. 2021. Concrete Ontology: Comments on Lauer, Little and Lohse. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 51: 40–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1993. The Advancement of Science: Science Without Legend, Objectivity without Illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., D. Ross, D. Spurret, and J. Collier. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. 2016. New Directions in the Philosophy of the Social Sciences. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markus, K., and D. Borsboom. 2013. Frontiers of Test Validity Theory: Measurement Causation and Meaning. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Messner, S., L. Raffalovich, and G. Sutton. 2010. Poverty, Infant Mortality and Homicide Rates in Cross-National Perspective: Assessments of Criterion and Construct Validity. Criminology 48: 509–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, Alyssa. 2012. Neo-Positivist Metaphysics. Philosophical Studies 160: 53–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northcott, R. 2015. Opinion Polling and Election Predictions. Philosophy of Science 82: 1260–1271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, Stathis. 1999. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1975. Mathematics, Matter and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1948. On What There Is. The Review of Metaphysics 2: 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1969. Existence and Quantification. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1986. Philosophy of Logic, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D., J. Ladyman, and H. Kincaid, eds. 2013. Scientific Metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruben, D. 2014. The Limits of Realism in the Philosophy of Social Science. In New Directions in the Philosophy of Science, eds. M.C. Galavotti et al., 313–322. Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saperstein, A. 2006. Double-Checking the Race Box: Examining Inconsistency between Survey Measures of Observed and Self-Reported Race. Social Forces 85: 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, D. 2019. Optimism for Naturalized Social Metaphysics: A Reply to Hawley. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 50: 138–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J., and J. Sprenger. 2011. The Logic of Explanatory Power. Philosophy of Science 78: 105–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, M., and G. Smith. 2009. Construct Validity: Advances in Theory and Methodology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 5: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taagepera, R. 2008. Making Social Sciences More Scientific: The Need for Predictive Models. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. 2015. An Introduction to Metametaphysics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. 2015. Ontology Made Easy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J.D. 1998. Measuring the Intentional World: Realism, Naturalism and Quantitative Methods in the Behavioral Sciences. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, P. 2013. A Confrontation with Convergent Realism. Philosophy of Science 80: 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R., and K. Pickett. 2006. Income Inequality and Population Health: A Review and Explanation of the Evidence. Social Science & Medicine 62: 1768–1784. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socscimed.2005.08.036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worall, J. 1989. Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds? Dialectica 43: 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. 1980. The Scientific Image. New York: Oxford Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J., and C. Finn. 2013. Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. New York: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article has received significant feedback from anonymous reviewers at two journals. Their feedback has markedly improved the quality of my discussion – they have my thanks (whoever they are).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Lauer.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lauer, R. Motivating a Pragmatic Approach to Naturalized Social Ontology. J Gen Philos Sci 53, 403–419 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-021-09581-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-021-09581-3

Keywords

Navigation