Skip to main content
Log in

United in Diversity: An Organic Overview of Non-Adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The non-adaptationist approach to evolutionary epistemology (EE) was born at the end of the 1970s as an alternative to traditional adaptationist EE. Despite the fact that non-adaptationist EE offers compelling interpretative models and its explanatory power is widely recognised, an organic overview of the broad non-adaptationist field is still lacking. In this paper, I propose to fill this gap. To this effect, after providing a systematisation of the perspectives that are commonly associated with non-adaptationist EE, I will discuss two recurring orders of arguments that non-adaptationist scholars, often independently of one another, put forward against their adaptationist rivals. By offering a way to conceive non-adaptationist evolutionary epistemological approaches as part of a structured whole, the resulting systematic account is meant to provide a reading grid, a compass for orienting oneself in the uneven territories of non-adaptationist EE. Moreover, the consequent identification of two recurring argumentative bodies is intended to add to the explanatory power of non-adaptationist EE, which in finding new strength in numbers eventually acquires a greater critical efficacy against its adaptationist counterpart.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Parts of this article have been submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the M.Sc. in History and Philosophy of Science at Utrecht University and have been extrapolated from my Master’s thesis “Evolution, Knowledge, and Reality: A Defence of Non-Adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology”, https://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/353294.

  2. Wuketits (1992, 1995, 2000) uses similar arguments to express his adherence to hypothetical realism. I think Wuketits’s endorsement of hypothetical realism is controversial, his position oscillating between two seemingly irreconcilable poles—realism and non-realism. In this paper, by centring in on the proximity of Wuketits’s position to that of Ruse (1989), I have interpreted Wuketits’s view in non-realist terms, as close to Ruse’s common-sense realist/internal realist standpoint. In light of this, whereas Wuketits’s (2006) reference to “something out there” might be read as a reiteration of a hypothetical realist stance, given Wuketits’s endorsement of Ruse’s ideas, it might also be interpreted as deriving from Ruse’s consideration that there are objects out there, but these are posited by us “in order to make sense of the coherence of our experience” (reviewed in Lemos 2002, 795). By focusing on the affinity between Wuketits’s position and Ruse’s, in this paper I opt for the second of these two readings.

  3. Riegler ascribes hypothetical realism to adaptationist thinkers and Wuketits (1992) as well. As I mentioned in footnote 2, Wuketits’s adherence to hypothetical realism is controversial, and it remains open to discussion whether Wuketits does in fact embrace a hypothetical realism of the kind espoused by adaptationist evolutionary epistemologists. In this paper, by centring in on the proximity of Wuketits’s position to that of Ruse (1989), I have read his view in non-realist terms, as close to Ruse’s common-sense realist/internal realist standpoint.

  4. The classic notion of knowledge as justified true belief (JTB) is the idea that “justified, true belief is necessary and sufficient for knowledge” (Ichikawa and Steup 2018). Accordingly, a subject “S knows that p if and only if p is true and S is justified in believing that p”, where “p” stands for “the proposition that is known” (Steup 2018). For a detailed analysis of the idea of knowledge as JTB, I refer the reader to Steup (2018) and Ichikawa and Steup (2018). Also of relevance is Cellucci’s proposal to rethink the JTB conception in view of elaborating a coherent naturalist and non-realist perspective on knowledge for which I refer the reader to Cellucci (2008) and Cellucci (2015). A full discussion of Cellucci’s ideas, also in comparison to non-adaptationist approaches to EE, goes beyond the scope of this article.

  5. Adaptationist thinkers do usually appeal to adaptation to solve this circularity and show that our knowledge is in fact reliable (cf. Vollmer 2004). As Sterpetti explains, adaptationist evolutionary epistemologists interpret adaptation as “a truth-encoding process” guided by natural selection, whereby natural selection is what “encode[s] in us true (or approximately true) knowledge about the world, or […] give[s] us a faculty which is able to reach some true (or approximately true) knowledge about the world in dealing with it” (Sterpetti 2011a, 185). In the light of this, truth of our (scientific) knowledge is guaranteed by natural selection and is “based on true features of the world” (ibid.). However, as Sterpetti argues:

    [A]daptationism itself can hardly guarantee the crucial assumption in the above argumentation: the fact that the relation between organisms and their environment [i.e., adaptation] can be seen as a sort of transfer of true knowledge, managed by selection, which is able to guarantee the product of our knowledge. This assumption can only be sustained by an IBE [(Inference to the Best Explanation)]. This is a “success-to-truth” inference, for which the survival of an organism implies his true (or approximately true) knowledge of its environment. (Sterpetti 2011a, 185)

    But, as Sterpetti notices, “[t]he appeal to evolution […] does not seem to be resolving”, since adaptationist evolutionary epistemologists end up presupposing what first should be demonstrated: “the connection between success and truth” (Sterpetti 2011b, 333-335, translation mine).

References

  • Campbell, D. T. (1959). Methodological suggestions from a comparative psychology of knowledge processes. Inquiry, 2(3), 152–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974). Evolutionary epistemology. In P. A. Schlipp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper (Vol. 1, pp. 413–459). Illinois: La Salle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. (2008). Perché ancora la filosofia. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. (2015). Rethinking knowledge. Metaphilosophy, 46(2), 214–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. J. (1986). Evolutionary epistemology and the scientific method. Philosophica, 37(1), 151–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., & Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary approaches to epistemic justification. Dialectica, 65(4), 517–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (1991). Induction and evolution of cognition and science. Philosophica, 47(2), 81–109. http://cepa.info/5156. Accessed 28 September 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (1992). Darwin, Lamarck and the evolution of science and culture. Evolution and Cognition, 1st Series, 2(3) (without page numbers). Available at: http://cepa.info/5157. Accessed 28 September 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (1998). On some relations between cognitive and biological evolution. In G. Van de Vijver, S. Salthe, & M. Delpos (Eds.), Evolutionary systems (pp. 319–340). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (2001). A physical approach to the construction of cognition and to cognitive evolution. Foundations of Science, 6(4), 273–341. Available at (without page numbers): http://cepa.info/4500. Accessed 28 September 2018.

  • Diettrich, O. (2004). Cognitive evolution. In F. M. Wuketits & C. Antweiler (Eds.), Handbook of evolution, Vol. 1: The evolution of human societies and cultures (pp. 25–75). Weinheim: Wiley-VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diettrich, O. (2006). The biological boundary conditions for our classical physical world view. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 67–93). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gontier, N. (2006a). Introduction to evolutionary epistemology, language and culture. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 1–29). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gontier, N. (2006b). Evolutionary epistemology. Internet encyclopaedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evo-epis/#H6. Accessed 13 November 2016.

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 205(1161), 581–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. J., & Steup, M. (2018). The analysis of knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/knowledge-analysis/.

  • Lemos, J. (2002). Theism, evolutionary epistemology, and two theories of truth. Zygon, 37(4), 789–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1941). Kant’s doctrine of the a priori in the light of contemporary biology. https://archive.org/details/KantsDoctrineOfTheAPrioriInTheLightOfContemporaryBiologyKonradLorenz. Accessed 6 November 2016.

  • Lorenz, K. (1977). Behind the mirror: A search for a natural history of human knowledge. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970). Genetic epistemology (E. Duckworth, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2001). Towards a radical constructivist understanding of science. Foundations of Science, 6(1–3), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2006). Like cats and dogs: Radical constructivism and evolutionary epistemology. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 47–65). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2007). Is Glasersfeld’s constructivism a dangerous intellectual tendency? In R. Glanville & A. Riegler (Eds.), The importance of being Ernst (pp. 263–275). Vienna: Echoraum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riegler, A. (2012). Constructivism. In L. L’Abate (Ed.), Paradigms in theory construction (pp. 235–255). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1986). Taking Darwin seriously. A naturalistic approach to philosophy. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1989). The view from somewhere: A critical defense of evolutionary epistemology. In K. Hahlweg & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Issues in evolutionary epistemology (pp. 185–228). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1998). Taking Darwin seriously: A naturalistic approach to philosophy. Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G. G. (1963). This view of life: The world of an evolutionist. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterpetti, F. (2011a). Between a bottom-up approach to mathematics and constructivism. L&PS – Logic and Philosophy of Science, 9(1), 181–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterpetti, F. (2011b). Il pluralismo evolutivo in relazione al problema mente-corpo (Doctoral dissertation). http://padis.uniroma1.it/bitstream/10805/1627/1/Fabio%20Sterpetti%20-%20Tesi%20di%20Dottorato%20-%20Il%20pluralismo%20evolutivo%20in%20relazione%20al%20problema%20mente-corpo.pdf. Accessed 12 June 2017.

  • Steup, M. (2018). Epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/epistemology/.

  • Vollmer, G. (1984). Mesocosm and objective knowledge: On problems solved by evolutionary epistemology. In F. M. Wuketits (Ed.), Concepts and approaches in evolutionary epistemology: Towards an evolutionary theory of knowledge (pp. 69–121). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (1987) [1975]. Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie (4th ed.). Stuttgart: Hirzel.

  • Vollmer, G. (2004). New arguments in evolutionary epistemology. Ludus Vitalis, 12(21), 197–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (1991). Fiktion und Realität aus der Perspektive des radikalen Konstruktivismus. In F. Roetzer & P. Weibel (Eds.), Strategien des Scheins (pp. 161–175). München: Klaus Boer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (1992). Adaptation, representation, construction: An issue in evolutionary epistemology. Evolution and Cognition, 2, 151–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (1995). A comment on some recent arguments in evolutionary epistemology – and some counterarguments. Biology and Philosophy, 10(3), 357–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (2000). Functional realism. In A. Carsetti (Ed.), Functional models of cognition (pp. 27–38). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wuketits, F. M. (2006). Evolutionary epistemology: The non-adaptationist approach. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, language and culture (pp. 33–46). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marta Facoetti.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Facoetti, M. United in Diversity: An Organic Overview of Non-Adaptationist Evolutionary Epistemology. J Gen Philos Sci 52, 211–225 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-019-09452-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-019-09452-y

Keywords

Navigation