Skip to main content
Log in

Identifying Pseudoscience: A Social Process Criterion

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many philosophers have come to believe there is no single criterion by which one can distinguish between a science and a pseudoscience. But it need not follow that no distinction can be made: a multifactorial account of what constitutes a pseudoscience remains possible. On this view, knowledge-seeking activities fall on a spectrum, with the clearly scientific at one end and the clearly non-scientific at the other. When proponents claim a clearly non-scientific activity to be scientific, it can be described as a pseudoscience. One feature of a scientific theory is that it forms part of a research tradition being actively pursued by a scientific community. If a theory lacks this form of epistemic warrant, this is a pro tanto reason to regard it as pseudoscientific.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For lists of such features, see, for example, the work of Mario Bunge (1991, 46) and Martin Mahner (2013, 38–39). (Bunge regards these features as jointly necessary, while Mahner favours a “family-resemblance” approach.)

  2. My spectrum resembles Pigliucci’s (2013, 18), but differs from it insofar as it does not label activities at the non-scientific end of the spectrum “pseudoscience,” for such activities are pseudoscientific only when they mimic science (see Sect. 1.2).

  3. Thagard later modified this view (1988, 168), but continued to acknowledge that it is not enough to examine the characteristics of theories; we need to look at the behaviour of the community that employs them. Indeed he went further, to discuss the communal nature of science and what he called “group rationality” (1988, 187).

  4. In 2015 Thomson Reuters removed this journal from its Journal Citation Reports because of its 71% self-citation rate (see https://archive.is/RFzYo), an indicator of pseudoscientific status that is consistent with what I am arguing here.

  5. While the present paper uses Laudan’s terminology of research traditions, the argument could be recast by reference to what Lakatos (1970) called research programmes. The feature in question would then be that of having been refused admission to, or excluded from, the relevant research programme.

  6. Even though the scientists who rejected the theory did not regard it as pseudoscientific, we may be able to do so, if there are those who continue to espouse it after its rejection by the relevant scientific community (see Sect. 4).

References

  • Barthes, R. (1967). Système de la mode. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and social imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., Blancke, S., & Pigliucci, M. (2015). What makes weird beliefs thrive? The epidemiology of pseudoscience. Philosophical Psychology, 28(8), 1177–1198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., & Braeckman, J. (2011). Immunizing strategies and epistemic defense mechanisms. Philosophia, 39(1), 145–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (1998). The role of funding agencies in the cognitive development of science. Research Policy, 27(8), 807–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1991). What is science? Does it matter to distinguish it from pseudoscience? A reply to my commentators. New Ideas in Psychology, 9(2), 245–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. W. (1975). The expanding earth: An essay review. Earth Sciences Review, 11(2), 105–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2011). The persistence of epistemic objects through scientific change. Erkenntnis, 75(3), 413–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donovan, A. (1996). Antoine Lavoisier: Science, administration and revolution. Cambridge Science Biographies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordin, M. D. (2012). The pseudoscience wars: Immanuel Velikovsky and the birth of the modern fringe. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. A. (2000). Evolutionary epistemology, social epistemology, and the demic structure of science. Biology and Philosophy, 15(3), 443–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2000). David Hull’s natural philosophy of science. Biology and Philosophy, 15(3), 301–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2017). Science and pseudo-science. In Zalta E. N. (ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/pseudo-science/.

  • Henson, P. M. (1988). A short note on Hull’s “A mechanism and its metaphysics: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science”. Biology and Philosophy, 3(2), 192–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hippocrates of Cos (1959). Hippocrates, tr. W. H. S. Jones, vol. 2. Loeb Classical Library. London: William Heinemann; Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Howard-Jones, N. (1977). Fracastoro and Henle: A re-appraisal of their contribution to the concept of communicable disease. Medical History, 21(1), 61–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The nature of science. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1988). Science as a process: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Science and its Conceptual Foundations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. Oxford Ethics Series. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge, N. (2013). Belief buddies versus critical communities. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Philosophy of pseudoscience: Reconsidering the demarcation problem (pp. 165–180). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1983). The demise of the demarcation problem. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (eds.), Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis: Essays in honor of Adolf Grünbaum (pp. 111–27). Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 76. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1994). The fate of knowledge in social theories of science. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 135–57). Studies in Epistemology and Cognitive Theory. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Lugg, A. (1987). Bunkum, flim-flam and quackery: Pseudoscience as a philosophical problem. Dialectica, 41(3), 221–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacLennan, A. H., & Morrison, R. G. B. (2012). Tertiary education institutions should not offer pseudoscientific medical courses. Medical Journal of Australia, 196(4), 225–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2007). Demarcating science from non-science. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: General philosophy of science—Focal issues (pp. 515–575). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2013). Science and pseudoscience: How to demarcate after the (alleged) demise of the demarcation problem. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Philosophy of pseudoscience: Reconsidering the demarcation problem (pp. 29–43). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, H. (1991). Tycho′s system and Galileo′s Dialogue. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A, 22(2), 259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, D. H. (1952). The celestial mechanics of electrically charged planets. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 96(5), 524–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1968). The Matthew effect in science. Science, NS 159(3810), 56–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1973). The normative structure of science. In N. W. Storer (Ed.), The sociology of science: Theoretical and empirical investigations (pp. 267–278). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (First published in 1942).

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, S. C. (2004). The origin of biological information and the higher taxonomic categories. Proceedings of the Biological Society of Washington, 117(2), 213–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R., & Sankey, H. (2000). A selective survey of theories of scientific method. In R. Nola & H. Sankey (Eds.), After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend: Recent issues in theories of scientific method (pp. 1–65). Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N. (1999). The rejection of continental drift: Theory and method in American earth science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1990). Virtus normativa: Rational choice perspectives. Ethics, 100(4), 725–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2013). The demarcation problem: A (belated) response to Laudan. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Philosophy of pseudoscience: Reconsidering the demarcation problem (pp. 9–28). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge Classics. London: Routledge. (First published in 1935).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ralph, P. (2016). Practical suggestions for improving scholarly peer review quality and reducing cycle times. Communications of the Association for Information Systems, 38(13), 274–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raup, D. M. (1986). The Nemesis affair: A story of the death of dinosaurs and the ways of science. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiefsky, M. J. (2005). Introduction. In M. J. Schiefsky (Ed.), Hippocrates of Cos, On Ancient Medicine (pp. 1–71). Studies in Ancient Medicine 28. Leiden: E. J. Brill.

  • Smith, R. (2006). Peer review: A flawed process at the heart of science and journals. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 99(4), 178–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (1994). Social empiricism. Noûs, 28(3), 325–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. A Bradford Book. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. R. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. A Bradford book. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. R. (1978). Why astrology is a pseudoscience. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Volume One: Contributed Papers, pp. 223–234.

  • Ziman, J. M. (1968). Public knowledge: An essay concerning the social dimension of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregory W. Dawes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dawes, G.W. Identifying Pseudoscience: A Social Process Criterion. J Gen Philos Sci 49, 283–298 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9388-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9388-6

Keywords

Navigation