Skip to main content
Log in

Demarcating the Realm of Cognition

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Extended Mind Hypothesis has given rise to stimulating philosophical debates about the boundaries of the realm of the cognitive. This paper first investigates the usefulness of a “mark of the cognitive,” and then focuses on two accounts that aim to provide such a mark, put forward by Fred Adams and Rebecca Garrison on one side and Mark Rowlands on the other. The paper provides a critical assessment of these accounts and uses empirical work on emotion regulation in infants to unearth some crucial challenges that any attempt at offering a mark of the cognitive should address.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This methodological choice fits well with the goals of cognitive science: if the goal is to shed light on the appropriate role in the explanation of behavior, then phenomenality is of relatively little relevance. As David Chalmers notes (1996, 11), “[f]rom the point of view of cognitive science, an internal state responsible for the causation of behavior is equally mental whether it is conscious or not” (see also Clark 1997).

  2. Both Rupert and Adams and Aizawa emphasize fine-grained features of human memory that EMH-systems lack (for instance the “generation effect”), while Adams and Aizawa (2008) and Fodor (2009) argue that argue that cognitive processes are exclusively realized by particular (neuronal) lower-level processes. Resisting the coarse-grained view, Adams and Aizawa (2008, 12) and Fodor (2009) argue that cognition-realizing substrates are mechanisms that function with “non-derived representations” and do not involve non-neuronal elements. Because non-derived representations exclusively occur in brain-bound systems, cognitive processes are brain-bound (Adams and Aizawa 2010).

  3. This includes quite mundane strategies like watching a comforting comedy to ease sadness, hitting the wall to diminish anger, “firing oneself up” before a big game, etc.

  4. There are interesting parallels to researchers like Theiner et al (2010), who argue that groups can exhibit emergent cognitive capacities. It is however important to note that dyadic interaction significantly differs from typical cases of group cognition, in part because it is not the outcome of a division of labor among agents based on shared goals.

  5. What counts as a cognitive process is mainly defined by the role it plays in the explanation of behavior, and thus includes including various forms of reasoning, memory, attention, problem solving, production of language. On such description, it is natural to think that emotion regulation belongs to the realm of the cognitive. This is also consistent with the manner in which the literature on emotion regulation speaks about “cognitive emotion regulation” and describes the relevant processes. For instance, cognitive reappraisal is often highlighted as the most successful general way to regulate emotions, next to situation selection, situation modification, attentional deployment, cognitive restructuring, and response modulation by expressive suppression (see McRae 2016). Thus, just as we regulate and sometimes successfully inhibit our thoughts from leading to behaviour, we regulate our emotions, for instance their intensity and duration to avoid maladaptive and behavior.

References

  • Adams, F. (2010). Why we still need a mark of the cognitive. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 324–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). Defending the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 67–80). Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Garrison, R. (2013). The mark of the cognitive. Minds and Machines, 23, 339–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. J. (2010). From cognition’s location to the epistemology of its nature. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 357–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brazelton, T. B., Koslowski, B., & Main, M. (1974). The origins of reciprocity: The early mother–infant interaction. In M. Lewis & L. A. Rosenblum (Eds.), The effect of the infant on its caregiver (pp. 49–76). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2015). A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 307–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2008). Foreword. In A. Clark (Ed.), Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension (pp. i–xv). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory, and the extended mind. Analysis, 65, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2011). Finding the mind. Philosophical Studies, 152, 447–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, P. M., Hall, S. E., & Radzioch, A. M. (2009). Emotional dysregulation and the development of serious misconduct. In S. L. Olson & A. J. Sameroff (Eds.), Biopsychosocial regulatory processes in the development of childhood behavioral problems (pp. 186–211). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Condon, W. S., & Sander, L. W. (1974). Synchrony demonstrated between movements of the neonate and adult speech. Child Development, 45, 456–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumas, G., Nadel, J., Soussignan, R., Martinerie, J., & Garnero, L. (2010). Inter-brain synchronization during social interaction. PLoS ONE, 5(8), e12166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elpidorou, A. (2014). Reasoning about the mark of the cognitive: A response to Adams and Garrison. Minds & Machines, 24, 201–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2007). On the origins of background emotions: From affect synchrony to symbolic expression. Emotion, 7(3), 601–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman R. (2012). Parent-infant synchrony: A biobehavioral model of mutual influences in the formation of affiliative bonds. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 77, 42–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Eidelman, A. I. (2004). Parent–infant synchrony and the social-emotional development of triplets. Developmental Psychology, 40, 1133–1147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2009). Where is my mind? London Review of Books, 31(3), 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, I., Zagoory-Sharon, O., Leckman, J. F., & Feldman, R. (2010). Oxytocin, cortisol, and triadic family interactions. Physiology and Behavior, 101, 679–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J. J. (2014). Emotion regulation: Conceptual and empirical foundations. In J. J. Gross (Ed.), Handbook of emotion regulation (2nd ed., pp. 3–20). New York, NY: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J. J., Richards, J. M., & John, O. P. (2006). Emotion regulation in everyday life. In D. K. Snyder, J. A. Simpson, & J. N. Hughes (Eds.), Emotion regulation in couples and families: Pathways to dysfunction and health. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J. J., Sheppes, G., & Urry, H. L. (2011). Emotion generation and emotion regulation: A distinction we should make (carefully). Cognition and Emotion, 25, 765–781.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ham, J., & Tronick, E. (2009). Relational psychophysiology: Lessons from mother-infant physiology research on dyadically expanded states of consciousness. Psychotherapy Research, 19, 619–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2014). Extended cognition & constitution: Re-evaluating the constitutive claim of extended cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 27(2), 258–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Extended cognition & the alleged causal-constitutive fallacy: In search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 320–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leclère, C., Viaux, S., Avril, M., Achard, C., Chetouani, M., Missonnier, S., et al. (2014). Why synchrony matters during mother-child interactions: A systematic review. PLoS ONE, 9(12), e113571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manian, N., & Bornstein, M. H. (2009). Dynamics of emotion regulation in infants of clinically depressed and nondepressed mothers. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 50(11), 1410–1418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McRae, K. (2016). Cognitive emotion regulation: A review of theory and scientific findings. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 10, 119–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Brooks, R. (2007). Intersubjectivity before language: Three windows on preverbal sharing. In S. Bråten (Ed.), On being moved: From mirror neurons to empathy (pp. 149–174). Philadelphia, PA: John.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Moore, G. A., & Calkins, S. D. (2004). Infants’ vagal regulation in the still-face paradigm is related to dyadic coordination of mother-infant interaction. Developmental Psychology, 40, 1068–1080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muratori, F., & Maestro, S. (2007). Autism as a downstream effect of primary difficulties in intersubjectivity interacting with abnormal development of brain connectivity. International Journal for Dialogical Science, 2, 93–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quoidbach, J., Berry, E., Hansenne, M., & Mikolajczak, M. (2010). Positive emotion regulation and well-being: Comparing the impact of eight savoring and dampening strategies. Personality and Individual Differences, 49, 368–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reck, C., Hunt, A., Weiss, R., Fuchs, T., Möhler, E., Downing, G., et al. (2004). Interactive regulation of affect in postpartum depressed mothers and their infants. Psychopathology, 3, 272–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2008). Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sansavini, A., Zavagli, V., Guarini, A., et al. (2015). Dyadic co-regulation, affective intensity and infant’s development at 12 months: A comparison among extremely preterm and full-term dyads. Infant Behavior and Development, 40, 29–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2011). Embodied cognition. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theiner, G., Allen, C., & Goldstone, R. L. (2010). Recognizing group cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11(4), 378–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1993). The self born in intersubjectivity: An infant communicating. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The perceived self: Ecological and interpersonal sources of self-knowledge (pp. 121–173). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (2002). Origins of musical identity: Evidence from infancy for musical social awareness. In R. A. R. MacDonald, D. J. Hargreaves, & D. Miell (Eds.), Musical identities (pp. 21–38). Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, E. Z. (1989). Emotions and emotional communication in infants. American Psychologist, 44, 112–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, E. Z. (1998). Dyadically expanded states of consciousness and the process of therapeutic change. Infant Mental Health Journal, 19(3), 290–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, E. Z. (2002). A model of infantmood states: Long lasting organizing affective states and emotional representational processes without language or symbols. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 12(1), 73–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Holland, M. (2013). Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive: Prospects of a proper function-based approach. Eindhoven: Technische Universiteit Eindhoven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2012). Non-reflective self-awareness. Do we need a situated account? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19(3–4), 164–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2016). Interaction and extended cognition. Synthese, 193(8), 2469–2496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walter, S., & Kästner, L. (2012). The where and what of cognition: The untenability of cognitive agnosticism and the limits of the Motley Crew Argument. Cognitive Systems Research, 13, 12–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, M. K., & Tronick, E. Z. (1994). Beyond the face: An empirical study of infant affective configurations of facial, vocal, gestural, and regulatory behaviors. Child Development, 65, 1495–1507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, M. K., Olson, K. L., Beeghly, M., & Tronick, E. Z. (2006). Making up is hard to do, especially for mothers with high levels of depressive symptoms and their infant sons. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 47, 670–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2010). In defense of extended functionalism. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 245–270). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Kriegel, U. (2015). For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not. In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology (pp. 36–53). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Somogy Varga.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Varga, S. Demarcating the Realm of Cognition. J Gen Philos Sci 49, 435–450 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9375-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9375-y

Keywords

Navigation