Skip to main content
Log in

Plants as Machines: History, Philosophy and Practical Consequences of an Idea

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper elucidates the philosophical origins of the conception of plants as machines and analyses the contemporary technical and ethical consequences of that thinking. First, we explain the historical relationship between the explicit animal machine thesis of Descartes and the implicit plant machine thesis of today. Our hypothesis is that, although it is rarely discussed, the plant machine thesis remains influential. We define the philosophical criteria for both a moderate and radical interpretation of the thesis. Then, assessing the compatibility of current botanical knowledge with both interpretations, we find that neither withstands scrutiny. We trace how biological and agricultural sciences have historically relied upon thinking of plants as machines and how they continue to do so today through rhetoric centred on breeding, biotechnology, and production. We discuss some of the most important legal and ethical consequences of obscuring the vitality of plants. Finally, we explore less reductive and destructive ways of thinking about, and using, plants.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of Data and Materials

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. ‘Machine’, CNRTL, Centre national de Ressources textuelles et lexicales. Retrieved October 18, 2021, from: https://www.cnrtl.fr/definition/machine. Author’s translation.

  2. In 1706, the Jesuits condemned the Cartesian thesis that animals do not have souls.

  3. Descartes himself practiced vivisection and justified it by his mechanical conception of life (Descartes, Letter to Plempius, February 15, 1638).

  4. For this term, see Shuman, V., Sander, D., Scherer, K. (2013) ‘Levels of Valence.’ Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 261.

  5. Sensitivity is a necessary condition for feeling pain, but it is not a sufficient one. Thus, a mechanical sensor, although it is a stimulation detection tool, does not suffer. For some philosophers, perception is the ordering of raw sensations, hence an interpretation or a minimal representation of the world. In this sense, a mechanical sensor is sensitive but not necessarily perceiving. However, this technical debate goes beyond our present conceptual framework.

  6. Western philosophers and theologians mostly considered plant souls to be mortal, whereas the immortality of animal souls was the subject of some debate.

  7. Phenotype: the observable characteristics of an organism, determined by the interaction between its genotype and environmental factors.

  8. Descartes’ interest in plants is evidenced in at least two places in his work (Primae cogitationes circa generationem animalium (AT XI 534–535) and Excerpta antomica (AT XI 627–629)). However, he did not seem to integrate them into his more general theories about life in any systematic way (Baldassarri, 2019).

  9. Alliance Forêts Bois, the leading forestry cooperative in France, created and managed by private forest owners. https://www.allianceforetsbois.fr/allianceinfos/. Author’s translation.

  10. Statements collected during an interview as part of an unpublished survey on representations of the plant world, conducted in 2018 among French professionals in plant research and the plant industry.

  11. ‘Phytotron.’ Office québécois de la langue française. Retrieved December 16, 2021. http://gdt.oqlf.gouv.qc.ca/ficheOqlf.aspx?Id_Fiche=26516468.

  12. INA, National Audiovisual Institute, video, 1961 ‘Botany is now joining chemistry’ https://www.ina.fr/video/CAF97059044/jean-paul-nitsch-le-phytotron-de-gif-sur-yvette-video.html INA video, 1964, ‘A reduced model of what happens in nature’ https://www.ina.fr/video/I06199394. The phytotron, CNRS video, 1969, https://videotheque.cnrs.fr/doc=1342.

  13. Base Web of Science, All databases, topic = phytotron, June 2021.

  14. ‘Published Plant Genomes’, Forschungszentrum Jülich. Retrieved December 16, 2021. https://www.plabipd.de/plant_genomes_pa.ep.

  15. Some contracts between agri-food manufacturers and farmers who provide raw materials indeed go so far as to ask for financial compensation from the farmers in case of a natural disaster reducing the planned production: https://www.sillonbelge.be/5696/article/2020-03-19/relation-avec-lagro-industrie-quelques-cles-pour-un-contrat-equilibre-et-sans.

  16. Banana trees are said to be parthenocarpic because they produce seedless fruits without fertilization.

References

  • Allen, C., & Trestman, M. (2020). Animal consciousness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/consciousness-animal/.

  • Alliance Infos. (2018) 14. Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://www.allianceforetsbois.fr/allianceinfos/.

  • Amzallag, G. N. (2003). L’Homme Végétal. Pour une autonomie du vivant. Albin Michel.

  • Andrews, K. (2016). Animal cognition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/cognition-animal/.

  • Andrews K., & Monsó, S. (2021). Animal cognition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/cognition-animal/.

  • Andrews, K. (2020). How to study animal minds. Cambridge University Press.

  • Aydede, M., (2019). Pain. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/pain/.

  • Baldassarri, F. (2019). The mechanical life of plants: Descartes on botany. The British Journal for the History of Science, 52(1), 41–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baril, C. (2001). Caractérisation variétale. Les marqueurs moléculaires: Un nouvel outil pour l’inscription et la protection variétale? Oléagineux, Corps Gras, Lipides, 8(5), 502–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Bich, L. (2021). Grounding cognition: Heterarchical control mechanisms in biology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0751

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benasayag, M. (2018). Fonctionner ou exister. Le Pommier.

  • Benharrech, S. (2022). Trees as dividual beings: Vegetal plurality in early modern France. Voyage to the Island of Mauritius (or Isle de France) (1773), Henri-Bernardin de Saint-Pierre (1737–1814). In N. Meeker, & A. Szabari (Eds.), Special Issue of L'Esprit créateur on ‘Libertine Botany’. Forthcoming in winter 2022.

  • Bernier, G. (2013). Darwin un pionnier de la physiologie végétale. L’apport de son fils Francis. Académie royale de Belgique.

  • Bertrand, A. (2018a). Le blé des physiocrates. Contribution à une histoire politique de l’ontologie végétale. Cahiers Philosophiques, 152, 9–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand, A. (2018b). Penser comme une plante: Perspectives sur l’écologie comportementale et la nature cognitive des plantes. Cahiers Philosophiques, 153(2), 39–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand, A. (2020a). Sociabilités végétales? Sens-Dessous, 26(2), 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand, A. (2020b). «Elle sera donc odeur de rose, d’oeillet, de jasmin, de violette»: l’attention au végétal et l’institution des collectifs, de Condillac à Descola et retour. Anthropologie Et Sociétés, 44(3), 109–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol-Hespériès, A. (1990). Le principe de vie chez Descartes. Vrin.

  • Blay, M. (Ed.). (2012). Grand dictionnaire de la philosophie. CNRS éditions.

  • Boisvert, V. (2016). Des limites de la mise en marché de l’environnement. Écologie Et Politique, 52, 63–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonneuil, C. (2016). Pure lines as industrial simulacra: A cultural history of genetics from Darwin to Johannsen’. In S. Mueller-Wille & C. Brandt (Eds.), Heredity explored. Between public domain and experimental science, 1850–1930 (pp. 213–242). MIT Press.

  • Bonneuil, C., & Thomas, F. (2009). Gènes, pouvoirs et profits: Recherche publique et régimes de production des savoirs de Mendel aux OGM. Quæ; Fondation pour le progrès de l’homme.

  • Bournérias, M., & Bock, C. (2006). Le génie des végétaux. Des conquérants fragiles. Belin.

  • Brunon, H. (2015). L’agentivité Des Plantes. Vacarme, 73(4), 118–123. https://doi.org/10.3917/vaca.073.0118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgat, F. (2006). Liberté et inquiétude de la vie animale. Kimé.

  • Burgat, F. (2020). Qu’est-ce qu’une plante? Seuil.

  • Canguilhem, G. (1965). Knowledge of life. Fordham University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2008). Meta-cognition in animals: A skeptical look. Mind & Language, 23, 58–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • CENH. (2008). The dignity of living beings with regard to plants. Moral consideration of plants for their own sake. Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://www.ekah.admin.ch/en/topics/dignity-of-living-beings/#c663.

  • Cesalpino, A. [1583] (2021). De Plantis Libri XVI. In Q. Hiernaux (Ed)., Textes-clés de Philosophie du végétal. Vrin.

  • Chouchan, N. (2018). Éditorial. Cahiers Philosophiques, 153(2), 5–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coccia, E. (2016). La vie des plantes. Une métaphysique du mélange. Payot et Rivages.

  • Cvrcková, F., Lipavská, H., & Žárský, V. (2009). Plant intelligence: Why, why not or where? Plant Signaling and Behavior, 4, 394–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagognet, F. (1970). Le catalogue de la vie. PUF.

  • Dagognet, F. (1988). La maîtrise du vivant. Hachette.

  • Darwin, C. (1865). On the movements and habits of climbing plants. Journal of the Linnean Society of London (botany), 9, 1–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, J. (2017). La domestication des plantes à l’échelle de la génomique. Jardins De France, 646, 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davy de Virville, A., & Leroy, J. F., et al. (1969a). Botanique à la Renaissance. In R. Taton (Ed.), La science moderne de 1450 à 1800 (pp. 177–187). Presses Universitaires de France.

  • Davy de Virville, A., & Leroy, J. F., et al. (1969b). Botanique au XVIIIe siècle. In R. Taton (Ed.), La science moderne de 1450 à 1800 (pp. 677–697). Presses Universitaires de France.

  • de Condillac, E. B. (1792). Traité des sensations, suivi du Traité des animaux [1755]. Les libraires associés.

  • de La Mettrie, J. O. [1748] (1996). Man as a plant. In A. Thomson (Ed.), Machine man and other writings (pp. 75–88). Cambridge University Press.

  • de Montaigne, M. [1580] (1877). Essays. William Carew Hazlitt, ed. Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://www.gutenberg.org/files/3600/3600-h/3600-h.htm#link2HCH0068.

  • Debono, M. W. (Ed.). (2020). L’intelligence des plantes en question. Hermann.

  • Degnen, C. (2009). On vegetable love: Gardening, plants, and people in the north of England. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 15(1), 151–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delaporte, F. [1979] (1982). Nature’s second Kingdom. Explorations of vegetability in the eighteenth century. MIT Press.

  • Deluermoz, Q., & Jarrige, F. (2017). Introduction. Écrire l’histoire avec les animaux. Revue D’histoire Du XIXe, 54, 15–29. https://doi.org/10.4000/rh19.5180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1637). Discours de la méthode (1637), Paris, Le Cerf (Adam et Tannery), 1902.

  • Descartes, R. (1638). Letter to Plempius, Feb 15, 1638.

  • Descartes, R. (1646). Lettre au marquis de Newcastle du 23 novembre 1646.

  • Descartes, R. (1647). Les principes de la philosophie (1647), Paris, Vrin, 1970.

  • Descartes, R. (1649). Lettre à Morus, Feb 5, 1649.

  • Dewey, J., & Bentley, A. F. (1949). Knowing and the known. Beacon Press.

  • Dewitte, J. (2002). L’anthropomorphisme, voie d’accès privilégiée au vivant. L’apport de Hans Jonas. Revue Philosophique De Louvain, 100(3), 437–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellul, J. (1976). (2004). La technique considérée en tant que système. Cahiers Jacques Ellul, Dossier: La Technique, 2, 49–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francione, G. (2000). Introduction to animal rights: Your child or the dog? Temple University Press.

  • Gagliano, M., Renton, M., Depczynski, M., & Mancuso, S. (2014). Experience teaches plants to learn faster and forget slower in environments where it matters. Oecologia, 175(1), 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gagliano, M., Vyazovskiy, V. V., Borbély, A. A., Grimonprez, M., & Depczynski, M. (2016). Learning by association in plants. Scientific Reports, 6, 38427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallais, A. (1989). Théorie de la sélection en amélioration des plantes. Masson.

  • Gaukroger, S. (1995). Descartes: An intellectual biography. Clarendon Press.

  • Georges-Berthier, A. (1914). Le mécanisme cartésien et la physiologie au XVIIe siècle. Isis, 2(1), 37–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, S. (2018). Les plantes cultivées cachent-elles la forêt? In Q. Hiernaux & B. Timmermans (Eds.), Philosophie du végétal (pp. 91–114). Vrin.

  • Ginglinger, J. F. (2018). PAT: les plantes que l’on peut traire. Conférence à l'Institut de botanique, Strasbourg.

  • Glémin, S., & Bataillon, T. (2009). A comparative view of the evolution of grasses under domestication. New Phytologist, 183(2), 273–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-8137.2009.02884.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruen, L. (2021). The moral status of animals. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/moral-animal/.

  • Guattari, F. (1993). Chaosmose. Galilée.

  • Guerra, S., Peressotti, A., Peressotti, F., et al. (2019). Flexible control of movement in plants. Science and Reports, 9, 16570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guichet, J. L. (Ed.). (2010). De l’animal machine à l’âme des machines – querelles biomécaniques de l’âme (XVIIe/XXIe siècles). Publications de la Sorbonne.

  • Guillaud, H. (2019). Défaire la tyrannie du numérique? Retrieved July 6, 2021, from http://www.internetactu.net/2019/10/23/defaire-la-tyrannie-du-numerique/.

  • Hache, É. (2011) Ce à quoi nous tenons - Propositions pour une écologie pragmatique. Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, Éditions La Découverte.

  • Hall, M. (2011). Plants as persons. SUNY Press.

  • Haraway, D. (2015). Anthropocene, capitalocene, plantationocene, chthulucene: Making kin. Environmental Humanities, 6, 159–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, R. (1992). Forests: The shadow of civilization. The University of Chicago Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. [1830] (2002). Philosophy of nature. Routledge.

  • Hermitte, M. H. (2016). L’emprise des droits intellectuels sur le monde vivant. Éditions Quæ.

  • Herrera, C. M. (2009). Multiplicity in unity. University of Chicago Press.

  • Hiernaux, Q. (2019). History and epistemology of plant behaviour: A pluralistic view? Synthese, 198(4), 3625–3650.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hiernaux, Q. (2020). Du comportement végétal à l’intelligence des plantes? Quæ.

  • Hiernaux, Q. (2021a). Differentiating behaviour, cognition, and consciousness in plants. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 28(1–2), 106–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiernaux, Q. (2021b). The ethics of plant flourishing and agricultural ethics: Theoretical distinctions and concrete recommendations in light of the environmental crisis. Philosophies, 6, 91. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6040091.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isabel, N., Holliday, J. A., & Aitken, S. N. (2019). Forest genomics: Advancing climate adaptation, forest health, productivity, and conservation. Evolutionary Applications, 13, 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Javelle, A., Kazic, D., & Tassin, J. (2020). Special issue “Repenser le statut des plantes”. La pensée écologique, 2(6).

  • Kallhoff, A., Di Paola, M., & Schörgenhumer, M. (Eds.). (2020). Plant ethics. Routledge.

  • Koechlin, F. (2009). The dignity of plants. Plant Signaling & Behavior, 4(1), 78–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N., & Brunero, J. (2020). Instrumental rationality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/rationality-instrumental/.

  • Kreutzer, M. (2017). L’éthologie. PUF.

  • Lalande, A. (1996). Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie. PUF.

  • Larrère, C. (1992). L’invention de l’économie au XVIIIe siècle; Du droit naturel à la physiocratie. PUF.

  • Larrère, C., & Larrère, R. (2005). Actualité de l’animal-machine. Les Temps Modernes, 2–3(630–631), 143–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lev-Yadun, S. (2008). Bioethics: On the road to absurd land. Plant Signaling & Behavior, 3(8), 612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieutaghi, P. (1998). La plante compagne. Actes sud.

  • Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning humane understanding (2nd ed.). Thomas Basset.

  • Louart, B. (2018). Les êtres vivants ne sont pas des machines. Collection Notes et morceaux choisis, La Lenteur. http://www.hobo-diffusion.com/catalogue/1664/notes-et-morceaux-choisis-13-notes-et-morceaux-choisis.

  • Maher, C. (2017). Plant minds: A philosophical defense. Routledge.

  • Mancuso, S., & Viola, A. (2015). Brilliant green. Island Press.

  • Marder, M. (2013). Is it ethical to eat plants? Parallax, 19(1), 29–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marder, M. (2014). For a phytocentrism to come. Environmental Philosophy, 11(2), 237–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munns, D. P. (2017). Engineering the environment: Phytotrons and the quest for climate control in the cold war. University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Myers, N. (2017). From the anthropocene to the planthroposcene: Designing gardens for plant/people involution. History and Anthropology. https://doi.org/10.1080/02757206.2017.1289934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2019). Is the cell really a machine? Journal of Theoretical Biology, 477, 108–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. A., & Stepp, J. R. (Eds.). (2016). Plants and health—New perspectives on the health-environment-plant Nexus. Springer.

  • Olson, R. (1990). Science defied and science deified: The historical significance of science in western culture. University of California Press.

  • Pouteau, S. (2014). Beyond ‘second animals’: Making sense of plant ethics. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 27(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pouteau, S. (2018). Plants as open beings: From aesthetics to plant–human ethics. In A. Kallhoff, M. Di Paola, & M. Schörgenhumer (Eds.), Plant ethics (pp. 82–97). Routledge.

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1979). La Nouvelle Alliance. Gallimard.

  • Raja, V., Silva, P. L., Holghoomi, R., et al. (2020). The dynamics of plant nutation. Science and Reports, 10, 19465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raven, P., Evert, R., & Eichorn, S. (2013). Biology of plants (8th ed.). Freeman and Company.

  • Renck, J.-L., Servais, V. (2002). L'éthologie. Histoire naturelle du comportement. Seuil.

  • Rousseau, J. J. [1776–1778] (1972). Les rêveries du promeneur solitaire. Gallimard.

  • Sauvagnargues, A. (2012). Machines, comment ça marche? Chimères, 2(77), 35–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A., & de Sousa, R. (2021). Emotion. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition). Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/emotion/.

  • Simondon, G. (1958). Du mode d’existence des objets techniques. Aubier.

  • Simonetti, V., Bulgheroni, M., Guerra, S., et al. (2021). Can plants move like animals? A three-dimensional stereovision analysis of movement in plants. Animals, 11, 1854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sniadecki, A. (2011). Malhonnêtetés et Fraudes de Darwin. Retrieved July 6, 2021, from https://sniadecki.wordpress.com/2011/04/02/critique-darwin-1/.

  • Sultan, S. (2015). Organism and environment: Ecological development, niche construction, and adaptation. Oxford University Press.

  • Thellier, M. (2015). Les plantes ont-elles une mémoire? Quæ.

  • Trewavas, A. (2014). Plant behaviour and intelligence. Oxford University Press.

  • Trewavas, A., Baluška, F., Mancuso, S., & Calvo, P. (2020). Consciousness facilitates plant behavior. Trends in Plant Science. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tplants.2019.12.015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, J. [1934] (1965). Mondes animaux et monde humain. Denoël.

  • von Linné, C. [1736] (2005). Fondements botaniques, qui, comme Prodrome à de plus amples travaux livrent la théorie de la science botanique par brefs aphorismes. Vuibert.

  • Wallace, A. R. (1858). On the tendency of varieties to depart indefinitely from the original type. Paper on natural selection sent by Wallace to Darwin. Retrieved July 6, 2021, from http://wallace-online.org/content/frameset?pageseq=1&itemID=S043&viewtype=text.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Juliette Archambeau, Cyril Firmat, the Émile Durckheim lab (University of Bordeaux) “Atelier environnement et capitalisme”, Didier Alard, Jérôme Santolini, Benoît Timmermans, Sarah Benharech, Thierry Labbé, Elis Jones and an anonymous reviewer for its useful comments.

Funding

This work was supported by the National Fund for Scientific Research (FNRS postdoctoral fellowship no 32740322) and by the National Research Institute for Agriculture, Food and Environment–INRAE.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Both authors contributed equally to all aspects of the article.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Quentin Hiernaux.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gerber, S., Hiernaux, Q. Plants as Machines: History, Philosophy and Practical Consequences of an Idea. J Agric Environ Ethics 35, 4 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-021-09877-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-021-09877-w

Keywords

Navigation