Skip to main content
Log in

Bearers of Transience: Simmel and Heidegger on Death and Immortality

  • Theoretical/Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article reconsiders the relationship between Simmel and Heidegger. Scholars commonly argue that Simmel’s work on the topic of death and mortality influenced the early Heidegger’s work on the same topic, as evidenced in Being and Time. I argue however that Simmel’s work particularly in the Lebensanschauung should be read as challenging the basic presuppositions of Heidegger on death. I then compare the two on the issue of immortality in order to show that Simmel is much closer to the subsequent critics of Heidegger than he is to Heidegger himself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the Phenomenology, the death in which Spirit maintains itself is described as pure contingency: “Death, if that is what we want to call this non-actuality[…]” (see Hegel 1976: 19).

  2. Simmel (1999: 232; 2010: 16): “Just as life’s transcendence, within the plane of life itself, of its current delimited form constitutes more-life (although it is nevertheless the immediate, inescapable essence of life itself), so also its transcendence into the level of objective content, of logically autonomous and no longer vital meaning, constitutes more-than-life, which is inseparable from it and is the essence of spiritual life itself”.

  3. Others (Krell, Jalbert) have noted that the thematic overlap of Being and Time and The View of Life arguably includes a whole set of interlocking philosophical concerns—from the effort to reinterpret the dynamic structure of life in a pretheoretical manner, and to recast the concept of time in terms of lived temporality, to the overarching concern to ground historical science in a novel understanding of historicity. In these and other ways, many have contended that Simmel and Heidegger remain closer than the latter was willing to admit (see Jalbert 2003: 259–283; Krell 1992: 93f.; Gawoll 1993: 193–151).

  4. The evidence supporting the view that Heideggerian Being-towards-death stems in part from Simmel consists in the testimony of Heidegger’s contemporaries, some of whom suggest that he had read and taken seriously relevant portions of The View of Life.

  5. On Heidegger’s critical stance toward the German historicist tradition, see Charles R. Bambach (1995).

  6. On the use of this term, see for instance Martin Heidegger (1995: 100).

  7. This is not to say that death is a latecomer in the early Heidegger. Though it goes unmentioned in the first Marburg seminar of 1923–1924, the analysis of uncanniness that punctuates these sessions paved the way for the emergence, months later, of Heidegger’s highly influential characterization of death as a way for human Dasein ‘to be’ (see 1994; 2005: 213f.).

  8. On Simmel’s use of the term ‘vital,’ see Daniel Silver, Monica Lee, and Robert Moore (2007: 262–290, esp. 269f.).

  9. This question becomes particularly pressing if we were to consider the genealogical sources feeding into Being-towards-death. According to Heidegger himself, the effort to stipulate Being-towards-death as how Dasein exists resulted from a critical re-interpretation of Aristotle’s ethical works, one which was informed by Heidegger’s reading of Christian sources. Subsequent to the publication of Being and Time, Heidegger indicated that the form of subjective certitude advanced in Division Two of Being and Time, of which Being-towards-death is a major component, is supposed to clarify Kant’s notion of the moral personality.

  10. Here the Kantian index is once again indispensable. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant defines anthropomorphism as the act of transforming subjective principles of cognition into objective determinations (see for example 2000: 227; AK 5: 353). He argues that we anthropomorphize when we mistake how we think about something for what that thing really is. On his reckoning symbols provide important information regarding how we depict objects, but they tell us very little, if anything at all, about the objects they presumably envisage. The error of anthropomorphism is most readily apparent when it comes to cognizing God. For Kant, all cognition of God, freedom, and immortality is symbolic. In order to think these three objects, the proper objects of metaphysics, we must analogize from the sensible or natural order. To use such analogies as though they reveal anything at all about these three objects, rather than our relation to them, is to extend our cognition unlawfully.

  11. Paul Ricoeur (2004: 350): “For Heidegger, death affects the self in its untransferable and incommunicable solitude: to assume this destiny is to bestow the seal of authenticity on the totality of experience thus placed in the shadow of death”; (2004: 356): “have not the resources of the openness of the potentiality-for-being been closed off by the insistence on the theme of death? Is not the tension between opening and closing attenuated by the dominion exercised, in fine, by being-toward-death treated as being toward a possibility?”

  12. It is absent, however, from the treatment of salvation Simmel develops elsewhere, in which salvation is distinguished from immortality as such (see [1903] 1997: 29–35).

  13. On this topic see Mari J. Molsee (1987: 357–366).

  14. This is the sense in which Heidegger speaks of death as the shrine of the nothing.

  15. Or Da-sein.

  16. On this point, see Matthew Lipman (1959: 128f.).

  17. On this topic see Ryan Coyne (2015).

References

  • Bambach, C. R. (1995). Heidegger, Dilthey, and the crisis of historicism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1995). Psychology from an empirical standpoint (O. Kraus, Ed., English edition L. L. McAlister, Ed., A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, & L. L. McAlister, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Coyne, R. (2015). Heidegger’s confessions: The remains of Saint Augustine in being and time and beyond. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1993). Aporias (T. Dutoit, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Frisby, D. (1986). Theories of modernity in the work of Simmel, Kracauer, and Benjamin. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (2013). Truth and method (2nd ed.). London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gawoll, H.-J. (1993). Impulse der Lebensphilosophie. Anmerkungen zum Verhältnis von Heidegger und Simmel. Simmel Newsletter, 3(2), 193–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1976). The phenomenology of spirit (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. MacQuarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 20: Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1984). Early Greek Thinking (D. F. Krell & F. A. Capuzzi, Trans.). New York: Harper and Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1985). History of the concept of time: Prolegomena (T. Kisiel, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1989). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 65: Beiträge zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis) (F.- W. von Herrmann, Ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, M. (1992). The concept of time (W. T. McNeil, Trans.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 59: Phänomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1994). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 17: Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (F.-W. von Herrmann, Ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 64: Der Begriff der Zeit (F.-W. von Hermann, Ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Off the beaten track (J. Young & K. Haynes, Eds. & Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2005). Introduction to phenomenological research (D. O. Dahlstrom, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Phenomenology of intuition and expression (T. Colony, Trans.). New York: Continuum.

  • Heidegger, M. (2012). Contributions to philosophy (of the event) (R. Rojcewicz & D. Vallega- Neu, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Jalbert, J. (2003). Time, death, and history in Simmel and Heidegger. Human Studies, 26(2), 259–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer, Ed., P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (2002). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics that will be able to come forward as science. In H. Allison & P. Heath (Eds.), Theoretical philosophy after 1781 (G. Hatfield, M. Friedman, H. Allison, & P. Heath, Trans.) (pp. 29–169). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kantorowicz, G. (1959). Preface to Georg Simmel’s fragments, posthumous essays, and publications of his last years. In K. H. Wolff (Ed.), Georg Simmel, 1858–1918: A collection of essays, with translations and a bibliography (pp. 3–8). Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, R. (2005). Georg Simmel. In G. Ritzer (Ed.), Blackwell’s encyclopedia of sociology (pp. 4323–4328). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kracauer, S. (1920). Georg Simmel. Logos, 9, 307–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krell, D. F. (1992). Daimon life: Heidegger and life philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and infinity (A. Lingis, Trans.). Pittsburgh: Duquesnes.

  • Levinas, E. (1987). Time and the other (R. Cohen, Trans.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1996). Basic philosophical writings (A. Peperzaak, S. Critchley, & R. Bernasconi, Eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Lipman, M. (1959). Some aspects of Simmel’s conception of the individual. In K. H. Wolff (Ed.), Georg Simmel, 1858–1918: A collection of essays, with translations and a bibliography (pp. 119–138). Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molsee, M. J. (1987). The problem of temporality in the work of Georg Simmel. The Sociological Quarterly, 28(3), 357–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (2004). Memory, history, forgetting (K. Blamey & D. Pellauer, Trans.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Silver, D., Lee, M., & Moore, R. (2007). The view of life: A Simmelian reading of Simmel’s ‘Testament’. Simmel Studies, 17(2), 262–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, G. ([1903] 1997). On the salvation of the soul. In H. J. Helle & L. Nieder (Eds. & Trans.), Essays on religion (pp. 29–35). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

  • Simmel, G. ([1911] 1997). The problem of religion today. In H. J. Hell & L. Nieder (Eds. & Trans.), Essays on religion (pp. 7–19). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Simmel, G. (1957). Brücke und Tür: Essays des Philosophen zur Geschichte, Religion, Kunst, und Gesellschaft (M. Landmann, Ed.). Stuttgart: K. F. Koehler Verlag.

  • Simmel, G. (1999). Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 16 (O. Rammstedt, Ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

  • Simmel, G. (2004). Fragmente aus dem nachgelassenen Tagebuche. In T. Karlsruehn & O. Rummstedt (Eds.), Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 20 (pp. 261–296). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

  • Simmel, G. (2010). The view of life: Four metaphysical essays with journal aphorisms (J. A. Y. Andrews & D. N. Levine, Trans.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan Coyne.

Additional information

The author wishes to dedicate this article to the memory of Donald N. Levine (1931–2015), who was, at the time of his death, the Peter B. Ritzma Professor Emeritus of Sociology at the University of Chicago.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Coyne, R. Bearers of Transience: Simmel and Heidegger on Death and Immortality. Hum Stud 41, 59–78 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9441-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9441-9

Keywords

Navigation