Skip to main content
Log in

Habermas on Understanding: Virtual Participation, Dialogue and the Universality of Truth

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although the success of Habermas’s theory of communicative action depends on his dialogical model of understanding in which a theorist is supposed to participate in the debate with the actors as a ‘virtual participant’ and seek context-transcendent truth through the exchange of speech acts, current literature on the theory of communicative action rarely touches on the difficulties it entails. In the first part of this paper, I will examine Habermas’s argument that understanding other cultural practices requires the interpreter to virtually participate in the “dialogue” with the actors as to the rationality of their cultural practice and discuss why, according to Habermas,such dialogue leads to the “context-transcendent truth”. In the second part, by using a concrete historical example, I will reconstruct a “virtual dialogue” between Habermas and Michael Polanyi as to the rationality of scientific practice and indicate why Habermas’s dialogical model of understanding based on the methodology of virtual participation cannot achieve what it professes to do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this respect, Habermas endorses Hacking’s (1999) argument that, unlike natural sciences, social sciences have “looping effects”. While natural scientific theories do not change what they are about, Hacking argues, social scientific theories circulate in and out of the practice they are about and thereby change that practice. The impossibility of maintaining the third person point of view emphasized in Habermas’s dialogical model attests to his conviction that social science is kind of “moral inquiry” that facilitates the development of the rational organization of society and culture. For a more detailed criticism of Hacking’s argument, see (Kim 2005).

  2. Although Habermas criticizes positivists for ignoring the fact that the actors’ world of meaning can be deciphered only ‘from within’ their action-context, he nonetheless argues that it does not necessarily mean that the interpreter must give up constructing a ‘causal hypothesis’ that explains why the actors believe what they do. This is why Habermas (1983) calls his approach interpretive social “science” as opposed to mere hermeneuticism. By contrast, Polanyi’s critique of positivism aims to show that the logic of scientific practice—being embodied in the tacit skills of the scientists—cannot be ‘represented’ in a causal proposition.

  3. For Borudieu, it is quite mistaken to ground reason, as Habermas does, in the “transhistorical” human nature (Bourdieu 1991: 21) because it fails to appreciate the fact that, rather than the “precondition” of rational consensus, reason is only the “end product” of the scientists’ selfish struggles for the monopoly of symbolic capital. It is true, Bourdieu argues, that scientific truth has universality. But such universality is made available only by virtue of the scientific field which has “historicity”. As I have argued elsewhere (Kim 2009), for Bourdieu, scientific truth is not “a disembodied or a transcendental concept but a collective thing embodied in a historically evolved social space called the scientific field”.

References

  • Bauman, Z. (1976). Towards a critical sociology: An essay on commonsense and emancipation. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics and praxis. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. (1985). Introduction. In R. Bernstein (Ed.), Habermas and modernity (pp. 1–32). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery (2nd ed.). London: RKP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1991). The peculiar history of scientific reason. Sociological Forum, 5, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (2000). Science of science and reflexivity. London: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (2003). Participant objectivation. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 9, 281–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. (1985). Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Grazia, A. (1963). The scientific reception system and Dr. Velikovsky. American Behavioral Scientist, 7(1), 45–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1983). Interpretive social science vs. hermeneuticism. In N. Haan (Ed.), Social science as moral inquiry (pp. 251–270). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action (Vol. I). Boston, MA: Beacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1985). Questions and counterquestions. In R. Berstein (Ed.), Habermas and modernity (pp. 192–216). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1990). The philosophical discourse of modernity: Twelve lectures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Coping with contingencies. In J. Niznik & J. T. Sanders (Eds.), Debating the state of philosophy: Habermas, Rorty, Kolakowski (pp. 1–30). Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1998). Between facts and norms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2000). Richard Rorty’s pragmatic turn. In R. Brandom (Ed.), Rorty and his critics (pp. 31–55). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammersely, M. (1992). What’s wrong with ethnography? London: RKP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollis, M. (1982). The social destruction of reality. In M. Hollis & S. Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and relativism (pp. 67–86). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoy, D. C. (1994). Critical theory and critical history. In D. C. Hoy & T. McCarthy (Eds.), Critical theory (pp. 101–214). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, K.-M. (2005). Discourses on liberation : An anatomy of critical theory. Boulder, CO: Paradigm.

  • Kim, K.-M. (2009). What would a Bourdieuan sociology of scientific truth look like? Social Science Information, 48, 57–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (1993). Scientific practice and ordinary action. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. (1985). Reflections on rationalization in the theory of communicative action. In R. Bernstein (Ed.), Habermas and modernity (176–191). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • McCarthy, T. (1988). Scientific rationality and the ‘strong programme in the sociology of knowledge. In E. McMullin (Ed.), Construction and constraint: The shaping of scientific rationality (pp. 75–96). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. (1994). Philosophy and critical theory: A reprise. In D. C. Hoy & T. McCarthy (Eds.), Critical theory (pp. 1–100). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1973). The sociology of science: Theoretical and empirical investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulkay, M. (1976). Norms and ideology in science. Social Science Information, 15, 637–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulkay, M. (1980). Sociology of science in the west. Current Sociology, 28, 1–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W. (1981). The rationality of science. London: Routledge and Keagn Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1967). The growth of science in society. Minerva, 5, 533–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2000). Universality and truth. In R. Brandom (Ed.), Rorty and his critics (pp. 1–30). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1958). The idea of social science and its relation to philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Stephen Tyler and the two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments on an earlier version of this article. The research for this paper has been supported by a research grant from Sogang University, grant number 201010052.01

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kyung-Man Kim.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kim, KM. Habermas on Understanding: Virtual Participation, Dialogue and the Universality of Truth. Hum Stud 34, 393–406 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-011-9200-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-011-9200-2

Keywords

Navigation