Skip to main content
Log in

The Hyle of Imagination and Reproductive Consciousness: Husserl’s Phenomenology of Phantasy Reconsidered

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The validity of Husserl’s early apprehension/content of apprehension schema (Auffassung/Auffassungsinhalt Schema) of intentionality has long been a subject of dispute. In the case of phantasy (Phantasie), commentators often assert that the talk of “non-intentional content,” i.e. the phantasm, is abandoned in Husserl’s mature phenomenology of phantasy, and his subsequent theory of reproductive consciousness aims precisely to replace the previous schema. Against the current dismissive stance in the literature, this paper argues for the centrality of the concept of phantasm in the phenomenology of phantasy. This is achieved in three steps. First, I argue for a functional interpretation of the schema, which maintains that it is not an empirical-genetic account of how non-intentional “sense-data” is transformed into presentations of intentional objects, but a structural exposition of the essential moments of objectifying consciousness. Second, I revisit Husserl’s theory of reproductive consciousness, arguing that in reproduction, what is reproduced is not only the noetic experience but also the hyletic substrate. Hence, the theory of reproductive consciousness, far from calling for an abandonment of the concept of phantasm, instead clarifies this concept and its function in phantasy. To fortify the point that the phantasm is crucial for the phenomenology of phantasy, I examine two features of phantasy, namely the perspectivalness of phantasized objects and the experience of my phantasy Ego being the “zero point of orientation” in phantasy, arguing that these two essential features can only be accounted for by appealing to the concept of phantasm.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Since our immediate goal is to restore the centrality of the phantasmatic content in the phenomenology of phantasy, a detailed analysis of the eidetic differences between image-consciousness, phantasy and (episodic) memory does not concern us in this paper. For this issue, see Jansen (2005a), de Warren (2009, 143–176), Aldea (2013) and Bernet (2020).

  2. In Ideas I, Husserl states clearly that the old expressions “sensation,” “sensoriness” etc. are inappropriate, for they mislead one to think that the only kind of non-intentional content is sensation, while in fact, “sensory feeling,” “drives” and, I shall add, the phantasm, should all be included, even though they are not “sensory” in the narrow sense. For this reason, he introduces the concept of “hyle” to replace the notion of sensory content. See Husserl (1976/2014, §85).

  3. For a detailed discussion of Gurwitsch’s view, see Drummond (1990), Chapter 4.

  4. For recent studies on the relationship between sensation (especially pain) and the constitution of the lived body, see Geniusas (2014) and (2020, 120–141).

  5. It should be noted that the term Vergegenwärtigung, which Jansen translates as “presentification,” is also translated as “representation” by some other commentators. Be that as it may, Jansen (and Husserl) does not mean that the noema of phantasy is some sort of mental representation. The concept of Vergegenwärtigung is used as a contrast to perceptual objects, which are “presentations” (Gegenwärtigungen), i.e. objects given as “bodily present” (leibhaftig). No representational theory of the mind is suggested.

  6. See also Zahavi (2015, 187).

  7. Indeed, this is the major textual reference for those criticizing the notion of the phantasm. See Jansen (2005b, 125), Płotka (2020, 42–43) and Marbach (1990, lx–lxiii). Marbach is among the first who points out that the analysis of time-consciousness and that of phantasy go hand in hand. For Marbach, it is through a critique of the schema as it is employed in the context of inner time-consciousness that Husserl becomes critical of the schema in the context of phantasy. To clarify, my point here is that, upon closer scrutiny, Husserl does not abandon the schema and the concept entirely, but only calls for a revision of how to construe and employ the schema. Also, as we will soon see, my point is not that the content-apprehension schema is universally applicable to all levels of conscious life. What I am arguing is that the schema is legitimate at higher level conscious life, i.e. at the objectifying level. Whether or not in the context of time-consciousness we can still employ the schema exceeds the scope of this paper. On this issue, see Brough (1972). For a discussion of time-consciousness and phantasy, see de Warren (2009, esp. 150–160) and Shum (2015, 224–227).

  8. It is worth pointing out that in his own analysis of the imagination, Sartre agrees with Husserl that the hyle of imagination must be accounted for. He also agrees with Husserl that the nature of the hyle of imagination is different from the hyle of perception (Sartre, 1950, 158). However, Sartre contends that the hyle of imagination cannot be tracked down by phenomenological analysis, and hence he turns to experimental psychology (Sartre, 1982, Part II). A comparison of Husserl and Sartre will take us too far afield. See Beata Stawarska (2005) for discussion.

  9. The original text reads, “… sinngebende (bzw. Sinngebung wesentlich implizierende) Schicht liegt, eine Schicht, durch die aus dem Sensuellen, das in sich nichts von Intentionalität hat, eben das konkrete intentionale Erlebnis zustande kommt.” Ideas I, §85.

  10. There are, of course, notable exceptions. Marco Cavallaro rejects the definition of phantasy in terms of reproduction and argues that phantasy is better understood as a phenomenon of Ego-splitting. He states that while Husserl initially conceptualizes phantasy as reproduction (as an intentional modification), he later criticizes this conception (Cavallaro, 2017). While his analysis of the phenomenon of Ego-splitting is insightful, his general position differs from mine on three counts. First, the manuscript that Cavallaro references does not reject that phantasy is a reproductive consciousness. Husserl’s point there is that there is, alongside image-consciousness and pure phantasy, a third form of “imagination” which he calls “perceptual phantasy.” This form of imagination is not a reproduction, but it does not mean that pure phantasy is not reproduction. For discussion of perceptual phantasy, see Bernet (2020, §2) and Javier Enrique Carreño Cobos (2013, 152–154). Second, as we will soon see, the doctrine of reproduction is not a doctrine of intentional modification; it is not a modification of the thetic character of an intentionality, but a peculiar form of modification which transforms the entirety of consciousness, not only affecting the thetic character. For this point, see the following (Sect. 5.3) and de Warren (2014). Third, as we will also see, the phenomenon of Ego-splitting is indeed a part of the structure of reproduction. See below, Sect. 5.2, and Bernet (2020, §4).

  11. It must be noted that (episodic) memory (Erinnerung), expectation etc. also fall under the heading of reproduction or reproductive consciousness. Phantasy is only one kind of reproductive consciousness. For discussion, see Bernet (2020, §3) and de Warren (2009, 167–176).

  12. For discussion of internal consciousness and self-awareness, see Zahavi (1999) (especially 14–37 and 63–90) and Zahavi (2003).

  13. Even though we can, in a sense, say that phantasy is phantasy “of” the perception of the object, the “of” here must not be understood as an intentional directedness. Briefly put, in phantasy, I do not have the perceptual experience as my intentional object, but the phantasy is a modification of the corresponding perceptual consciousness. For this reason, I put the “of” here in scare quotes. We shall explain the difference between an intentional “of” and the “of” which belongs properly to phantasy later, in Sect. 5.3.

  14. It should be noted that in a quite different context, Husserl employs the language of “Ego-splitting” to capture something quite different. For instance, in the Cartesian Meditations, Husserl explicitly uses the term when he talks about the split of the “ego” of the practicing phenomenologist when she reflects on her experience, a usage which might be related but is not equivalent to the phenomenon of interest here. He writes, “If the Ego, as naturally immersed in the world, experiencingly and otherwise, is called ‘interested’ in the world, then the phenomenologically altered—and, as so altered, continually maintained—attitude consists in a splitting of the Ego: in that the phenomenological Ego establishes himself as ‘disinterested onlooker,’ above the naively interested Ego” (Husserl, 1950, 73, 1967, 35). See also Husserl (1965, 86–90, 2019, 290–294).

  15. In the original passage, de Warren translates Husserl’s term Phantasie as imagination. I slightly modify the quote, using “phantasy” to replace “imagination” in order to keep the terminological consistency of this paper.

  16. For Husserl’s theory of thetic character and modality, see the Logical Investigations, the Fifth Investigation, Chapter I and II. See also Ideas I, §§103–114.

  17. Saulius Geniusas helpfully distinguishes three different senses of reproduction and argues that phantasy is a reproduction of an act of experiencing (das Erleben). See Geniusas (2020, 139–140).

  18. See also Shum (2015, 228–229).

  19. As Nicolas de Warren points out, “les apparitions imaginaires se réfèrent à un «moi imaginaire» (Phantasie-Ich) ayant une incarnation indéterminée ou un «corps-fantôme», et même si le corps fantôme est indéterminé, il possède néanmoins ce degré-zéro d’orientation vis-à-vis duquel les objets imaginaires sont donnés dans un quasi-espace (mais aussi dans un quasi-temps).” (de Warren, 2006, para. 29).

References

  • Aldea, A. S. (2013). Husserl’s Struggle with Mental Images: Imaging and Imagining Reconsidered. Continental Philosophy Review, 46, 371–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernet, R. (2020). Mapping the Imagination: Distinct Acts, Objects, and Modalities. Husserl Studies, 36(3), 213–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brough, J. (1972). The Emergence of an Absolute Consciousness in Husserl’s Early Writings on Time-consciousness. Man and World, 5(3), 298–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreño Cobos, J.E. (2013). The many senses of imagination and the manifestation of fiction: A view from Husserl’s phenomenology of phantasy. Husserl Studies, 29, 143–162

  • Cavallaro, M. (2017). The Phenomenon of Ego-splitting in Husserl’s Phenomenology of Pure Phantasy. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 48(2), 162–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christian, B. M., Parkinson, C., Macrae, C. N., Miles, L. K., & Wheatley, T. (2015). When Imagining Yourself in Pain, Visual Perspective Matters: The Neural and Behavioral Correlates of Simulated Sensory Experiences. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 27(5), 866–875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Warren, N. (2006). Imagination et incarnation. Methodos (9), http://journals.openedition.org/methodos/2148; https://doi.org/10.4000/methodos.2148.

  • de Warren, N. (2009). Husserl and The Promise of Time: Subjectivity in Transcendental Phenomenology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Warren, N. (2014). Towards a Phenomenological Analysis of Virtual Fictions. Metodo. International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy, 2(2), 91–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. J. (1990). Husserlian Intentionality and Non-foundational Realism. Kluwer.

  • Gallagher, S. (1986). Hyletic Experience and the Lived Body. Husserl Studies, 3, 131–166.

  • Geniusas, S. (2014). The Subject of Pain: Husserl’s Discovery of the Lived-Body. Research in Phenomenology, 44, 384–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geniusas, S. (2017). Pain and Intentionality. In R. Walton, S. Taguchi, & R. Rubio (Eds.), Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology (pp. 113–136). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geniusas, S. (2020). The Phenomenology of Pain. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1964). The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1950). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge. S. Strasser (Ed). Husserliana I. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zur einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. M. Biemel (Ed.). Husserliana IV. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1965). Erste Philosophie (1923/24). Zweiter Teil: Theorie Der Phänomenologischen Reduktion. R. Boehm (Ed.). Husserliana VIII. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1967). Cartesian Meditations. D. Cairns (Trans.). The Hague: Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins (1893–1917). R. Boehm (Ed.). Husserliana X. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch, K. Schuhmann (Ed.). Husserliana III/1. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1980). Phantasie, Bildbewusstsein, Erinnerung. Zur Phänomenologie der anschaulichen Vergegenwärtigung. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1891–1925), E. Marbach (Ed.). Husserliana XXIII. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Teil: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Band 2. U. Panzer (Ed.). Husserliana XIX/2. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Rojcewicz R (trans.). Springer: Dordrecht.

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917). J. B. Brough (Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical Investigations, Two volumes. J. N. Findlay (Trans.), D. Moran (Eds.). London: Routledge.

  • Husserl, E. (2005). Phantasy, image consciousness, and memory (1898–1925). J. B. Brough (Trans.). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Husserl, E. (2014). Ideas for Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (trans.). Cambridge: Hackett.

  • Husserl, E. (2019). First Philosophy: Lectures 1923/24 and Related Texts from the Manuscripts (1920–1925). Translated by S. Luft and Thane M. Naberhaus. Netherlands: Springer.

  • Jansen, J. (2005a). Phantasy’s Systematic Place in Husserl’s Work. In R. Bernet, D. Welton, & G. Zavota (Eds.), Edmund Husserl: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers (Vol. 3, pp. 221–243). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, J. (2005b). On the Development of Husserl’s Transcendental Phenomenology of Imagination and its Use for Interdisciplinary Research. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(2), 121–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, J. (2010). Phenomenology, Imagination and Interdisciplinary Research. In S. Gallagher & D. Schmicking (Eds.), Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science (pp. 141–158). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, J. (2013). Imagination, Embodiment and Situatedness: Using Husserl to Dispel (Some) Notions of “Off-Line Thinking.” In R. T. Jensen & D. Moran (Eds.), The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity (pp. 63–79). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, J. (2016). Husserl. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 69–81). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, D. (2002). Husserl’s Concept of Categorial Intuition. In D. Zahavi & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.), One Hundred Years of Phenomenology: Husserl’s Logical Investigations Revisited (pp. 125–145). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marbach, E. (1990). Einleitung to Hua XXIII. In E. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewusstsein, Erinnerung. Zur Phänomenologie der anschaulichen Vergegenwärtigung. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1891– 1925), E. Marbach (Ed.). Husserliana XXIII. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • McKenna, W. (2005). The Problem of Sense Data in Husserl’s Theory of Perception. In R. Bernet, D. Welton, & G. Zavota (Eds.), Edmund Husserl: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers (Vol. 3, pp. 145–158). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Płotka, W. (2020). A Controversy Over the Existence of Fictional Objects: Husserl and Ingarden on Imagination and Fiction. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 51(1), 33–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1950). L’imagination. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France; The Imagination, K. Williford and D. Rudrauf (Trans.). New York: Routledge, 2012.

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1982). L’imaginaire. Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination. Paris: Gallimard; The Imaginary, J. Webber (Trans.). New York: Routledge, 2004.

  • Shum, P. (2015). The Evolution and Implications of Husserl’s Account of the Imagination. Husserl Studies, 31, 213–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Q. (1977). A Phenomenological Examination of Husserl’s Theory of Hyletic data. Philosophy Today, 21, 356–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. (1970). The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stawarska, B. (2005). Defining imagination: Sartre between Husserl and Janet. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(2), 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williford, K. (2013). Husserl’s Hyletic Data and Phenomenal Consciousness. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, 12, 501–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation. Northwestern University Press.

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Inner time-consciousness and pre-reflective self-awareness. In D. Welton (Ed.), The New Husserl: A Critical Reader (pp. 157–180). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2015). Phenomenology of reflection. In Andrea Staiti (Ed.), Commentary on Husserl’s Ideas I (pp. 177–194). Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter.

Download references

Funding

The authors did not receive support from any organization for the submitted work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ka-yu Hui.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hui, Ky. The Hyle of Imagination and Reproductive Consciousness: Husserl’s Phenomenology of Phantasy Reconsidered. Husserl Stud 38, 273–292 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-022-09308-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-022-09308-2

Navigation