Skip to main content
Log in

Brain, Mind, World: Predictive Coding, Neo-Kantianism, and Transcendental Idealism

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recently, a number of neuroscientists and philosophers have taken the so-called predictive coding approach to support a form of radical neuro-representationalism, according to which the content of our conscious experiences is a neural construct, a brain-generated simulation. There is remarkable similarity between this account and ideas found in and developed by German neo-Kantians in the mid-nineteenth century. Some of the neo-Kantians eventually came to have doubts about the cogency and internal consistency of the representationalist framework they were operating within. In this paper, I will first argue that some of these concerns ought to be taken seriously by contemporary proponents of predictive coding. After having done so, I will turn to phenomenology. As we shall see, Husserl’s endorsement of transcendental idealism was partially motivated by his rejection of representationalism and phenomenalism and by his attempt to safeguard the objectivity of the world of experience. This confronts us with an intriguing question. Which position is best able to accommodate our natural inclination for realism: Contemporary neuro-representationalism or Husserl’s transcendental idealism?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Swanson further argues that predictive coding theory can be “seen as a major step in the evolution of Kant’s transcendental psychology” (2016, p. 10), though he also acknowledges that the former’s evolutionary, computational and neuroscientific approach “goes beyond Kant’s insights in ways that Kant could not have imagined” (2016, p. 11). One might wonder, though, whether the naturalism of predictive coding theory is not ultimately incompatible with Kant’s transcendental framework. For a critical take on the possibility of naturalizing Kant, see Allison (1995). For a more general discussion of whether naturalism and transcendental philosophy can be reconciled, see Zahavi (2004, 2013).

  2. One reason for these continuing disagreements is not only that people tend to employ notions such as “direct”, “indirect”, and “immediate” in quite different ways, but also that there has been a tendency to conflate epistemic, experiential, and causal understanding of these terms. The presence of causal intermediaries does not necessarily entail that perception is experientially and/or epistemically indirect. Likewise, the fact that our perceptual access to spatio-temporal objects in the world is enabled and underpinned by various sub-personal mechanisms and non-conscious cognitive processes does not necessarily entail that we therefore fail to see the objects as they are in themselves. Rather, one might view the cognitive processing as that which makes it possible for us to experience those objects in the first place (Hopp 2011, p. 163).

  3. Let me add that neuro-representationalism can obviously also be found outside of the predictive coding framework. For a prominent example, see Grush (2003).

  4. I am indebted to helpful comments from Liesbet de Kock and John Michael.

References

  • Allison, H. E. (1995). On naturalizing Kant’s transcendental psychology. Dialectica, 49(2–4), 335–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allison, H. E. (2015). From transcendental realism to transcendental idealism: The nature and significance of Kant’s ‘transcendental turn’. In S. Gardner & M. Grist (Eds.), The transcendental turn (pp. 20–34). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L., & Chemero, T. (2013). The problem with brain GUTs: Conflation of different senses of ‘prediction’ threatens metaphysical disaster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 204–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2016). The anticipating brain is not a scientist: The free-energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1239-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgar, S. (2013). The limits of experience and explanation: F.A. Lange and Ernst Mach on things in themselves. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21(1), 100–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fichte, J.G. (1988). Early philosophical writings. D. Breazeale (Trans.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free–energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. (2007). Making up the mind: How the brain creates our mental worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Allen, M. (2016). Active inference, enactivism and the hermeneutics of social cognition. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1269-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 53–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. (2010 [1830]). Encyclopedia of the philosophical sciences in basic outline. Part I: Science of logic. K. Brinkmann and D. O. Dahlstrom (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1985 [1925]). History of the concept of time. T. Kisiel (Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Helmholtz, H.v. (1855). Das Sehen des Menschen. Leipzig: Leopold Voss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H.v. (1995 [1853/1892]). Science and culture: Popular and philosophical lectures. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

  • Hobson, J. A., & Friston, K. J. (2014). Consciousness, dreams, and inference: The Cartesian theatre revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(1–2), 6–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2016). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs, 50(2), 259–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopp, W. (2011). Perception and knowledge: A phenomenological account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960 [1929/1950]). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. D. Cairns (Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1982 [1913]). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. First book. General introduction to a pure phenomenology. F. Kersten (Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (2003). Transzendentaler Idealismus. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1921). Husserliana 36. R. Rollinger (Ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Jacobi, F. H. (2000 [1787]). On transcendental idealism. In B. Sassen (Ed.), Kant’s early critics: The empiricist critique of the theoretical philosophy (pp. 169–175). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (1998 [1787]). Critique of pure reason. P. Guyer and A. W. Wood (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (2005 [1785-1789]). Notes and fragments. C. Bowman, P. Guyer, F. Rauscher (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kock, L. D. (2014). Hermann von Helmholtz’s empirico-transcendentalism reconsidered: Construction and constitution in Helmholtz’s psychology of the object. Science in Context, 27(4), 709–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kock, L. D. (2016). Helmholtz’s Kant revisited. The all-pervasive nature of Helmholtz’s struggle with Kant’s Anschauung. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 56, 20–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, F. A. (1925 [1865]). The history of materialism and criticism of its present importance. E. C. Thomas (Trans.). London: Kegan Paul.

  • Mach, E. (1895 [1882]). The economical nature of physical inquiry. In Popular scientific lectures. Th. J. McCormack (Trans.). Chicago: Open Court.

  • Metzinger, T. (2009). The ego tunnel. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, J. (1842). Elements of physiology II. W. Baly (Trans.). London: Taylor and Walton

  • Putnam, H. (1987). The many faces of realism. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1970) [1939]. Intentionality: A fundamental idea of Husserl’s phenomenology. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 1(2), 4–5.

  • Slaby, J., & Heilinger, J.-C. (2013). Lost in phenospace: Questioning the claims of popular neurophilosophy. Metodo, 1(2), 83–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, L. R. (2016). The predictive processing paradigm has roots in Kant. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 10(79), 1–13. doi:10.3389/fnsys.2016.00079.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Phenomenology and metaphysics. In D. Zahavi, S. Heinämaa, & H. Ruin (Eds.), Metaphysics, facticity, interpretation (pp. 3–22). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2004). Phenomenology and the project of naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(4), 331–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2008). Internalism, externalism, and transcendental idealism. Synthese, 160(3), 355–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2010). Husserl and the ‘absolute’. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences: Essays in commemoration of Husserl (pp. 71–92). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Zahavi, D. (2013). Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 72, 23–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2017). Husserl’s legacy: Phenomenology, metaphysics, and transcendental idealism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan Zahavi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zahavi, D. Brain, Mind, World: Predictive Coding, Neo-Kantianism, and Transcendental Idealism. Husserl Stud 34, 47–61 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-017-9218-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-017-9218-z

Navigation