Skip to main content
Log in

The Need for Authenticity-Based Autonomy in Medical Ethics

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The notion of respect for autonomy dominates bioethical discussion, though what qualifies precisely as autonomous action is notoriously elusive. In recent decades, the notion of autonomy in medical contexts has often been defined in opposition to the notion of autonomy favoured by theoretical philosophers. Where many contemporary theoretical accounts of autonomy place emphasis on a condition of “authenticity”, the special relation a desire must have to the self, bioethicists often regard such a focus as irrelevant to the concerns of medical ethics, and too stringent for use in practical contexts. I argue, however, that the very condition of authenticity that forms a focus in theoretical philosophy is also essential to autonomy and competence in medical ethics. After tracing the contours of contemporary authenticity-based theories of autonomy, I consider and respond to objections against the incorporation of a notion of authenticity into accounts of autonomy designed for use in medical contexts. By looking at the typical problems that arise when making judgments concerning autonomy or competence in a medical setting, I reveal the need for a condition of authenticity—as a means of protecting choices, particularly high-stakes choices, from being restricted or overridden on the basis of intersubjective disagreement. I then turn to the treatment of false and contestable beliefs, arguing that it is only through reference to authenticity that we can make important distinctions in this domain. Finally, I consider a potential problem with my proposed approach; its ability to deal with anorexic and depressive desires.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Frankfurt doesn’t use the term autonomy here, but his theory as outlined is often referred to as a theory of autonomy (see Taylor 2005), and when he began later to explicitly write about the notion of autonomy, he utilized the same hierarchical account (Bratman 2007).

  2. Hierarchical theories of autonomy are sometimes thought to require explicit reflection on the basis of second-order desires, but this is something proponents of hierarchical theories sought to avoid (see Frankfurt 1971; Dworkin 1988). I will thus focus on correspondence rather than reflective acceptance in what follows.

  3. For an account of the various problems faced by hierarchical theories of autonomy, and the various ways that subsequent theories of autonomy have been developed to avoid these problems (see Taylor 2005).

  4. For examples of the ways that this type of theory of autonomy actually incorporate the Lockean self (see Bratman 2007; Ekstrom 2005).

  5. As will be further elucidated below, Faden and Beauchamp want their account of autonomy to be focused on actions, not persons. It is for this reason that they speak of an action being autonomous, rather than, as is more common in the theoretical literature, a person being autonomous with respect to her action.

  6. More on this distinction below.

  7. Again, we will look at this in more detail below.

  8. I use the term “intersubjective” rather than “external” or “objective” here and in what follows because I want to stress that there is no objective standard by which the content of someone’s values and goals can be criticized—when we criticize the content of others’ values and goals, we are doing so from our own conception of rationality, wellbeing, etc., or from standards that have achieved widespread intersubjective agreement in our society (see Wolf 1987).

  9. This approach might also show promise for Faden and Beauchamp’s condition of noncontrol—they themselves suggest that a condition of authenticity shows the most promise when it comes to adequately capturing both external and internal controlling influences (1986). However, an adequate assessment of this complicated concept is beyond the scope of this paper.

  10. The so-called “Gettier Problem” reveals just how vexing some of these issues can be (see Gettier 1963).

  11. Faden and Beauchamp also provide a third example here: “Nothing good can come of my consenting to this procedure, because no matter what new skills and coping styles I might develop, I will never want to live as a quadriplegic.” This is a particularly difficult case, and one that has attracted considerable attention in the existing literature (see, e.g., Savulescu 1994; Cowart and Burt 1998). Without getting into the details of this nuanced issue, I believe such a case can be satisfactorily dealt with by my proposed approach, by first making an effort to dispel unrealistically negative conceptions of what it means to be a quadriplegic (see Savulescu 1994), but, after reasonable efforts have been made, accepting the patient’s decision to refuse treatment on the basis of his enduring values.

  12. This need not fundamentally change the purpose of autonomy or competence requirements; we could view these decisions as prima facie worthy of special respect and protection, but able to overridden in exceptional circumstances. Indeed, this is the role that Faden and Beauchamp envision for autonomous decisions.

  13. Many thanks to Dietmar Hübner and two anonymous referees from the HEC Forum for their useful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Benson, P. (2005). Feminist intuitions and the normative substance of autonomy. In J. Taylor (Ed.), Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy (pp. 124–142). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2007). Planning agency, autonomous agency. In M. Bratman (Ed.), Structures of agency (pp. 195–221). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D. (1991). Decision making competence and risk. Bioethics, 5(2), 105–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., & Brock, D. (1986). Deciding for others. The Milbank Quarterly, 64(Suppl. 2), 17–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charland, L. (2006). Anorexia and the MacCAT-T test for mental competence: Validity, value and emotion. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 13(4), 283–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowart, D., & Burt, R. (1998). Confronting death: Who chooses, who controls? The Hastings Center Report, 28(1), 14–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drane, J. (1984). Competency to give an informed consent. Journal of the American Medical Association, 252(7), 925–927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drane, J. (1985). The many faces of competency. The Hastings Center Report, 15(2), 17–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, L. (2005). Autonomy and personal integration. In J. Taylor (Ed.), Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy (pp. 143–161). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eth, S., Eth, C., & Edgar, H. (1981). Can a research subject be too eager to consent? The Hastings Center Report, 11(1), 20–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faden, R., & Beauchamp, T. (1986). A history and theory of informed consent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gert, B., Culver, C., & Clouser, K. (2006). Bioethics: A systematic approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grisso, T., & Appelbaum, P. (1995). Comparison of standards for assessing patients’ capacities to make treatment decisions. American Journal of Psychiatry, 152(7), 1033–1037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grisso, T., & Appelbaum, P. (1998). Assessing competence to consent to treatment: A guide for physicians and other health professionals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grisso, T., & Appelbaum, P. (2006). Appreciating anorexia: Decisional capacity and the role of values. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 13(4), 293–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindmarch, T., Hotopf, M., & Owen, G. (2013). Depression and decision-making capacity for treatment or research: A systematic review. BMC Medical Ethics, 14(54), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewy, E. (1988). Changing one’s mind: When is Odysseus to be believed? Journal of Geriatric Internal Medicine, 3(1), 54–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markson, L., Kern, D., Annas, G., & Glantz, L. (1994). Physician assessment of patient competence. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 42(10), 1074–1080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nestler, E., Barrot, M., DiLeone, R., Eisch, A., Gold, S., & Monteggia, L. (2002). Neurobiology of depression. Neuron, 34(1), 13–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, R. (2005). Autonomy and the paradox of self-creation. In J. Taylor (Ed.), Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy (pp. 143–161). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudnik, A. (2002). Depression and competence to refuse psychiatric treatment. Journal of Medical Ethics, 28(3), 151–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. (1994). Rational desires and the limitation of life-sustaining treatment. Bioethics, 8(3), 191–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skene, L. (1991). Risk-related standard inevitable in assessing competence. Bioethics, 5(2), 113–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, M., & Youngner, S. (1994). Depression, competence, and the right to refuse lifesaving medical treatment. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 151(7), 971–978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swindell, J. (2009). Two types of autonomy. The American Journal of Bioethics, 9(1), 52–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tan, J., Stewart, A., Fitzpatrick, R., & Hope, R. (2006). Competence to make treatment decisions in anorexia nervosa: Thinking processes and values. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 13(4), 267–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J. (2005). Introduction. In J. Taylor (Ed.), Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy (pp. 1–29). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Varelius, J. (2011). Decision-making competence and respect for patient autonomy. Res Cogitans, 8(1), 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmann, J. (2006). “But I don’t feel it”: Values and emotions in the assessment of patients with anorexia nervosa. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 13(4), 289–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, L. (2017). How autonomy can legitimate beneficial coercion. In J. Gather, T. Henking, A. Nossek & J. Vollmann (Eds.), Beneficial coercion in psychiatry? Foundations and challenges (pp. 85–99). Münster: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1987). Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character and emotions: New essays on moral psychology (pp. 46–62). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucie White.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

White, L. The Need for Authenticity-Based Autonomy in Medical Ethics. HEC Forum 30, 191–209 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-017-9335-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-017-9335-2

Keywords

Navigation