Skip to main content
Log in

An Ontology of Nature with Local Causality, Parallel Lives, and Many Relative Worlds

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Parallel lives (PL) is an ontological model of nature in which quantum mechanics and special relativity are unified in a single universe with a single space-time. Point-like objects called lives are the only fundamental objects in this space-time, and they propagate at or below c, and interact with one another only locally at point-like events in space-time, very much like classical point particles. Lives are not alive in any sense, nor do they possess consciousness or any agency to make decisions—they are simply point objects which encode memory at events in space-time. The only causes and effects in the universe occur when lives meet locally, and thus the causal structure of interaction events in space-time is Lorentz invariant. Each life traces a continuous world-line through space-time, and experiences its own relative world, fully defined by the outcomes of past events along its world-line (never superpositions), which are encoded in its external memory. A quantum field comprises a continuum of lives throughout space-time, and familiar physical systems like particles each comprise a sub-continuum of the lives of the field. Each life carries a hidden internal memory containing a local relative wavefunction, which is a local piece of a pure universal wavefunction, but it is the relative wavefunctions in the local memories throughout space-time which are physically real in PL, and not the universal wavefunction in configuration space. Furthermore, while the universal wavefunction tracks the average behavior of the lives of a system, it fails to track their individual dynamics and trajectories. There is always a preferred separable basis, and for an irreducible physical system, each orthogonal term in this basis is a different relative world—each containing some fraction of the lives of the system. The relative wavefunctions in the lives’ internal memories govern which lives of different systems can meet during future local interactions, and thereby enforce entanglement correlations—including Bell inequality violations. These, and many other details, are explored here, but several aspects of this framework are not yet fleshed out, and work is ongoing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The model presented here has grown outside of the other versions, and the distinction between ‘lives’ and ‘relative worlds’ is new.

  2. More on the single-system approximation later.

  3. Noting again that in most classical situations, we can treat macroscopic systems as having their own collective lives, even though this is only approximation to the true microscopic story.

References

  1. Einstein, A.: Relativity: The Special and the General Theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2015)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Aharonov, Y., Rohrlich, D.: Quantum Paradoxes: Quantum Theory for the Perplexed. Wiley, Hoboken (2008)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Brassard, G., Raymond-Robichaud, P.: Can free will emerge from determinism in quantum theory? In: Is Science Compatible with Free Will? pp. 41–61, Springer, New York (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Waegell, M.: Locally causal and deterministic interpretations of quantum mechanics: parallel lives and cosmic inflation. Quantum Stud. 4, 323–337 (2017)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Brassard, G., Raymond-Robichaud, P.: Parallel lives: a local-realistic interpretation of “nonlocal” boxes. arXiv:1709.10016 (2017)

  6. Brassard, G., Raymond-Robichaud, P.: The equivalence of local-realistic and no-signalling theories. arXiv:1710.01380 (2017)

  7. Zurek, W.H.: Algorithmic information content, church-turing thesis, physical entropy, and Maxwell’s demon. Technical report, Los Alamos National Laboratory, NM (1990)

  8. Atmanspacher, H.: Determinism is ontic, determinability is epistemic. In: Between Chance and Choice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Determinism, pp. 49–74 (2002)

  9. Przibram, K., Schrödinger, E., Einstein, A., Lorentz, H.A., Planck, M.: Letters on Wave Mechanics. Vision Press, London (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Norsen, T.: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics: An Exploration of the Physical Meaning of Quantum Theory. Springer, New York (2017)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: Many worlds and Schrödinger’s first quantum theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 62(1), 1–27 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Everett III, H.: “relative state” formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 29(3), 454 (1957)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Everett III, H.: The theory of the universal wave function. In: The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Citeseer, Princeton (1973)

  14. DeWitt, B.S., Graham, N.: The Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2015)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Wallace, D.: Worlds in the Everett interpretation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 33(4), 637–661 (2002)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  17. Wallace, D.: Decoherence and ontology: or: how I learned to stop worrying and love FAPP. In: Many Worlds, pp. 53–72 (2010)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  18. Wallace, D.: Everett and structure. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 34(1), 87–105 (2003)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Saunders, S.: Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory, & Reality. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Vaidman, L.: Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. https://seop.illc.uva.nl/entries/qm-manyworlds (2002)

  21. Sebens, C.T., Carroll, S.M.: Self-locating uncertainty and the origin of probability in everettian quantum mechanics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 69, 25–74 (2014)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Deutsch, D., Hayden, P.: Information flow in entangled quantum systems. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A 456, 1759–1774 (2000)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Timpson, C.G.: Nonlocality and information flow: the approach of Deutsch and Hayden. Found. Phys. 35(2), 313–343 (2005)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Wallace, D., Timpson, C.G.: Quantum mechanics on spacetime I: spacetime state realism. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 61(4), 697–727 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Brown, H.R., Timpson, C.G.: Bell on bell’s theorem: The changing face of nonlocality. arXiv:1501.03521 (2014)

  26. Albert, D., Loewer, B.: Interpreting the many worlds interpretation. Synthese 77(2), 195–213 (1988)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. Bohm, D.: A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. i. Phys. Rev. 85(2), 166 (1952)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Holland, P.R.: The Quantum Theory of Motion: An Account of the de Broglie–Bohm Causal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Wyatt, R.E.: Quantum Dynamics with Trajectories: Introduction to Quantum Hydrodynamics, vol. 28. Springer, New York (2006)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Hiley, B.J., Dubois, D.M.: Non-commutative geometry, the Bohm interpretation and the mind–matter relationship. AIP Conf. Proc. 573, 77–88 (2001)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  31. Griffiths, R.B.: Consistent Quantum Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.B.: Decoherent histories quantum mechanics with one real fine-grained history. Phys. Rev. A 85(6), 062120 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  33. Hall, M.J., Deckert, D.-A., Wiseman, H.M.: Quantum phenomena modeled by interactions between many classical worlds. Phys. Rev. X 4(4), 041013 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Madelung, E.: The hydrodynamical picture of quantum theory. Z. Phys. 40, 322–326 (1926)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  35. Trahan, C.J., Wyatt, R.E., Poirier, B.: Multidimensional quantum trajectories: applications of the derivative propagation method. J. Chem. Phys. 122(16), 164104 (2005)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  36. Schiff, J., Poirier, B.: Communication: Quantum Mechanics Without Wavefunctions (2012)

  37. Elitzur, A.C., Vaidman, L.: Quantum mechanical interaction-free measurements. Found. Phys. 23(7), 987–997 (1993)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  38. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47(10), 777 (1935)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  39. Bell, J.S.: On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 38(3), 447 (1966)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  40. Bell, J.S.: The theory of local beables. In: John S. Bell on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 50–60, World Scientific, Singapore (2001)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  41. Bell, J.S.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: Collected Papers on Quantum Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  42. Wigner, E.P.: Remarks on the mind-body question. In: Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses, pp. 247–260, Springer, New York (1995)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  43. Minkowski, H.: Space and Time: Minkowski’s Papers on Relativity. Minkowski Institute Press, Montreal (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kochen, S., Specker, E.P.: The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 17(1), 59–87 (1967)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  45. Spekkens, R.W.: Contextuality for preparations, transformations, and unsharp measurements. Phys. Rev. A 71(5), 052108 (2005)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  46. Robinson, A.: Non-standard Analysis. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Albeverio, S.: Nonstandard Methods in Sochastic Analysis and Mathematical Physics, vol. 122. Academic Press, Cambrigde (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  48. Joos, E., Zeh, H.D., Kiefer, C., Giulini, D.J., Kupsch, J., Stamatescu, I.-O.: Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory. Springer, New York (2013)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  49. Zurek, W.H.: Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical. Rev. Mod. Phys. 75(3), 715 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  50. Schlosshauer, M.: Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 76(4), 1267 (2005)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  51. Zurek, W.H.: Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical—revisited. In: Quantum Decoherence, pp. 1–31. Springer, New York (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  52. Popescu, S., Rohrlich, D.: Quantum nonlocality as an axiom. Found. Phys. 24(3), 379–385 (1994)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  53. Cirel’son, B.S.: Quantum generalizations of Bell’s inequality. Lett. Math. Phys. 4(2), 93–100 (1980)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  54. Heisenberg, W.K.: The uncertainty principle. In: The World of the Atom, vol. 1. Edited with commentaries by Henry A. Boorse and Lloyd Motz, with a foreword by II Rabi, p. 1094. Basic Books, New York (1966)

  55. Frauchiger, D., Renner, R.: Single-world interpretations of quantum theory cannot be self-consistent. arXiv:1604.07422 (2016)

  56. Aharonov, Y., Albert, D.Z., Vaidman, L.: How the result of a measurement of a component of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle can turn out to be 100. Phys. Rev. Lett. 60(14), 1351 (1988)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  57. Dressel, J.: Weak values as interference phenomena. Phys. Rev. A 91(3), 032116 (2015)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  58. Kim, Y.-H., Yu, R., Kulik, S.P., Shih, Y., Scully, M.O.: Delayed “choice” quantum eraser. Phys/ Rev. Lett. 84(1), 1 (2000)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  59. Scully, M.O., Drühl, K.: Quantum eraser: a proposed photon correlation experiment concerning observation and “delayed choice” in quantum mechanics. Phys. Rev. A 25(4), 2208 (1982)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  60. Hensen, B., Bernien, H., Dréau, A.E., Reiserer, A., Kalb, N., Blok, M.S., Ruitenberg, J., Vermeulen, R.F., Schouten, R.N., Abellán, C., et al.: Loophole-free bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres. Nature 526(7575), 682 (2015)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  61. Fuchs, C.A., Schack, R.: A quantum-bayesian route to quantum-state space. Found. Phys. 41(3), 345–356 (2011)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  62. Fuchs, C.A., Schack, R.: Quantum-Bayesian coherence. Rev. Mod. Phys. 85(4), 1693 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  63. Fuchs, C.A., Mermin, N.D., Schack, R.: An introduction to qbism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. Am. J. Phys. 82(8), 749–754 (2014)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  64. Harrigan, N., Spekkens, R.W.: Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states. Found. Phys. 40(2), 125–157 (2010)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  65. Aharonov, Y., Bohm, D.: Significance of electromagnetic potentials in the quantum theory. Phys. Rev. 115(3), 485 (1959)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  66. Doran, C., Lasenby, A., Gull, S.: Gravity as a gauge theory in the spacetime algebra. In: Clifford Algebras and Their Applications in Mathematical Physics, pp. 375–385. Springer, New York (1993)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  67. Lasenby, A., Doran, C., Gull, S.: Cosmological consequences of a flat-space theory of gravity. In: Clifford Algebras and Their Applications in Mathematical Physics, pp. 387–396. Springer, New York (1993)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  68. Lasenby, A., Doran, C., Gull, S.: Gravity, gauge theories and geometric algebra. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. A 356(1737), 487–582 (1998)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  69. Hestenes, D.: Gauge theory gravity with geometric calculus. Found. Phys. 35(6), 903–970 (2005)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  70. Hsu, J.-P.: Yang–Mills gravity in flat space-time I: classical gravity with translation gauge symmetry. Int. J. Mod. Phys. A 21(25), 5119–5139 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  71. Hestenes, D.: Gauge gravity and electroweak theory. In: The Eleventh Marcel Grossmann Meeting On Recent Developments in Theoretical and Experimental General Relativity, Gravitation and Relativistic Field Theories, pp. 629–647 (2008)

  72. Hsu, J.-P.: A unified gravity-electroweak model based on a generalized Yang–Mills framework. Mod. Phys. Lett. A 26(23), 1707–1718 (2011)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  73. Hsu, J.-P.: A model of unified quantum chromodynamics and Yang–Mills gravity. Chin. Phys. C 36(5), 403 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  74. Hsu, J.-P.: Space-time translational gauge identities in Abelian Yang–Mills gravity. Eur. Phys. J. Plus 3(127), 1–8 (2012)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  75. Wigner, E.P.: On hidden variables and quantum mechanical probabilities. Am. J. Phys. 38(8), 1005–1009 (1970)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  76. Mermin, N.D.: Is the moon there when nobody looks? Reality and the quantum theory. Phys. Today 38(4), 38–47 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank all of the following researchers for humoring me through many discussions as these ideas solidified. In no particular order, they are: Walter Lawrence, David Cyganski, Justin Dressel, Matt Leifer, Kevin Vanslette, Luis Pedro García-Pintos, Kelvin McQueen, Roman Buniy, Paul Raymond-Robichaud, Yakir Aharonov, Jeff Tollaksen, Taylor Lee Patti, Travis Norsen, and Gregg Jaeger. This research was supported (in part) by the Fetzer Franklin Fund of the John E. Fetzer Memorial Trust.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mordecai Waegell.

Appendix

Appendix

There are many details that one must become comfortable with before the elegance of this model becomes obvious, and toward this end, I have devised a classroom exercise for a group of students that will allow them to participate in a simulation of the local entanglement mechanism themselves, and violate a Bell inequality.

Some of the students in the exercise will acts as lives of different systems, while others will play the role of nature, and act as referees, who read and write from the memories of different students, and determine which lives can meet. In general, we will need the same number of students to acts as lives for every physical system we want to simulate, and we can keep the minimum total number small by restricting ourselves to only a few simple measurement settings—since each student technically represents an infinite number of lives, and we need to divide the lives into the right proportions. To simulate space-like separation, students cannot communicate directly during the exercise.

Each student who represents lives of a system will carry a notebook. The notebook contains a label for which system they belong to, like ‘qubit 1,’ and they also contain pages for internal memory, and other pages for external memory. Due to the initial interaction of the two systems, each student starts off with a pure quantum state \(|\psi \rangle \) in their internal memory, which includes every system in the past interaction cone of the system. Furthermore, each student has one of the outcomes \(|a\rangle ^1|b\rangle ^2\) of the interaction encoded in their external memory (which defines the preferred basis), along with a history of outcomes of past interactions for all other systems \(|c\rangle ^o\) in the past interaction cone. The proportion of students in each of these relative worlds is \(P(a,b,c) = |\langle \psi |a\rangle |b\rangle |c\rangle |^2\).

Now, suppose that system 1 interacts via unitary U with a new system 3, and the students of each system meet one-to-one. The referee now reads the internal memories \(|\psi _1\rangle \) and \(|\psi _3\rangle \) of an interacting pair of students from each system, and then updates them both to contain the relative state \(|\psi '\rangle = U |\psi _1\rangle |\psi _3\rangle \). The interaction may also cause the preferred basis to change, and then each student encodes an outcome \(|x\rangle ^1|y\rangle ^3\) in that basis into their external memory (which determines which relative world they experience), and the pair shake hands to signify their meeting event. Just as before, the proportion of students in each relative world is given by \(P(x,y,z) = |\langle \psi |x\rangle |y\rangle |z\rangle |^2\), where again \(|z\rangle ^o\) is the history state of other systems, which includes the outcome of the previous interaction between systems 1 and 2, and the referee pairs the students off according to these proportions.

When macro-scale systems meet, the interaction unitary is identity, and the preferred bases do not change, but their lives still synchronize their internal memories and encode the meeting into their external memories. These are the only rules we need in order to simulate a Bell experiment.

Let us consider one of the classic examples, developed by Wigner [75] and Mermin [76], of a Bell test involving a source which prepares two qubits in the singlet state \(|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2} = \big (|0\rangle ^1|1\rangle ^2 - |1\rangle ^1|0\rangle ^2 \big )/\sqrt{(}2)\), and sends one to Alice and one to Bob. We assume that we can ignore other systems in the interaction history of these two at the beginning of this experiment. At space-like separation, Alice and Bob randomly choose among the three equally spaced angles in the XZ-plane and measure the qubit along that axis. For this simulation we will need 16 students to act as lives, and 3 to acts as local referees. We will begin with this state already prepared, and let \(\{|0\rangle ,|1\rangle \}\) be the preferred basis for both systems. Each qubit will have 8 students representing it, and this means that 4 students of qubit 1 are in state \(|0\rangle ^1\) have a record in their external memory of meeting a student of qubit 2 in state \(|1\rangle ^2\), and the other four are in state \(|1\rangle ^1\) and met a student of qubit 2 in state \(|0\rangle ^2\). All 16 of them have \(|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2}\) written in internal memory.

Now, the 8 students of qubit 1 walk over to Alice, and the 8 students of qubit 2 to Bob. For simplicity, we let setting 1 be the already-preferred basis, and settings 2 and 3 be, \(\left\{ \frac{\sqrt{3}}{2}|0\rangle + \frac{1}{2}|1\rangle , \frac{1}{2}|0\rangle - \frac{\sqrt{3}}{2} |1\rangle \right\} \), and \(\left\{ \frac{\sqrt{3}}{2}|0\rangle - \frac{1}{2}|1\rangle , \frac{1}{2}|0\rangle + \frac{\sqrt{3}}{2} |1\rangle \right\} \), respectively. We will let Alice begin in the ready state \(|R\rangle ^A\), and the interaction unitary is then \(U^{1,A} = |s_1\rangle ^A |s_1\rangle ^1 \langle R|^A \langle s_1|^1 + |s_2\rangle ^A |s_2\rangle ^1 \langle R|^A \langle s_2|^1 +\) (terms with \(\langle R_\bot |^A\)), where \(|s_1\rangle \) and \(|s_2\rangle \) are the basis states of the measurement setting, and similar for Bob’s \(U^{2,B}\).

If Alice chooses setting 1, then 4 of her students meet a student of qubit 1 already in state \(|0\rangle ^1\) and experience outcome \(|0\rangle ^A\), and the other 4 meet a student already in state \(|1\rangle ^1\) and experience outcome \(|1\rangle ^A\). Using \(P(s_1^1, s_1^A, h^2)\), we see that if Alice measures either setting 2 or 3, then three students of qubit 1 which were previously in the relative world \(|0\rangle ^1\) now enter relative world \(|s_2\rangle ^1\) and meet students of Alice in state \(|s_2\rangle ^A\), one student of qubit 1 which was previously in the relative world \(|0\rangle ^1\) now enters relative world \(|s_1\rangle ^1\) and meets a student of Alice in state \(|s_1\rangle ^A\), three students of qubit 1 which were previously in the relative world \(|1\rangle ^1\) now enter relative world \(|s_1\rangle ^1\) and meet students of Alice in state \(|s_1\rangle ^A\), and one student of qubit 1 which was previously in the relative world \(|1\rangle ^1\) now enters relative world \(|s_2\rangle ^1\) and meets a student of Alice in state \(|s_2\rangle ^A\).

For any setting, the referee then writes the outcomes in the external memory of the students of both Alice and qubit 1, and the state \(|\psi ^{1,2,A} \rangle = U^{1,A}|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2}|R\rangle ^A\) in their internal memories. To save on students during the measurement interaction, the same 8 students playing lives of qubit 1 now also play lives of Alice, and after the interaction they continue as lives of Alice.

The situation is symmetrically identical for Bob, so after the measurement, his 8 students will now have \(|\psi ^{1,2,B}\rangle = U^{2,B}|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2}|R\rangle ^B\) written in their internal memories.

Now Alice’s 8 students and Bob’s 8 students reunite. When two systems meet, their internal memories synchronize by accumulating all states and coupling unitaries from both of their past internal memories. When students of Alice and Bob meet, their internal memories synchronize to \(|\psi \rangle ^{1,2,A,B} = U^{1,A} U^{2,B}|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2}|R\rangle ^A |R\rangle ^B\), and their preferred bases remain the same, so the proportion of students in each relative world who meet is given by \(P(s_a, s_b, h) = |\langle \psi |^{1,2,A,B} | s_a\rangle ^A | s_b\rangle ^B |h\rangle ^{1,2}|^2 = |\langle \psi _0|^{1,2} | s_a\rangle ^1 | s_b\rangle ^2 |^2\) , where \(s_a\) is the ath outcome of Alice’s measurement, and \(s_b\) is the bth outcome of the Bob’s measurement, and \(|h\rangle ^{1,2}\) is the most recent external memory state of qubits 1 and 2 within the history h. The proportion of lives that meet with each pair of specific histories is determined using Eq. 3.

If Alice and Bob measured the same setting, then four students of Alice who got \(|s_1\rangle ^A\) each meet a student of Bob who got \(|s_2\rangle ^B\), and four students of Alice who got \(|s_2\rangle ^A\) each meet a student of Bob who got \(|s_1\rangle ^B\). If they measured different settings, then three of Alice’s students who got \(|s_1\rangle ^A\) each meet a student of Bob who got \(|s_1\rangle ^B\), one of Alice’s students who got \(|s_1\rangle ^A\) meets a student of Bob who got \(|s_2\rangle ^B\), three of Alice’s students who got \(|s_2\rangle ^A\) each meet a student of Bob who got \(|s_2\rangle ^B\), and one of Alice’s students who got \(|s_2\rangle ^A\) meets a student of Bob who got \(|s_1\rangle ^B\). In any case, it is easy to see that the entanglement correlations of the initial state \(|\psi _0\rangle ^{1,2}\) have been obeyed for the entire group of students.

Then, by repeating the exercise many times, an individual student will experience Born rule statistics and thus a violation of a Bell inequality, even though everything was done obeying explicit local causality.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Waegell, M. An Ontology of Nature with Local Causality, Parallel Lives, and Many Relative Worlds. Found Phys 48, 1698–1730 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-018-0222-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-018-0222-8

Keywords

Navigation