Skip to main content
Log in

Less Decoherence and More Coherence in Quantum Gravity, Inflationary Cosmology and Elsewhere

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Crull (Found Phys 45:1019–1045, 2015) it is argued that, in order to confront outstanding problems in cosmology and quantum gravity, interpretational aspects of quantum theory can by bypassed because decoherence is able to resolve them. As a result, Crull (Found Phys 45:1019–1045, 2015) concludes that our focus on conceptual and interpretational issues, while dealing with such matters in Okon and Sudarsky (Found Phys 44:114–143, 2014), is avoidable and even pernicious. Here we will defend our position by showing in detail why decoherence does not help in the resolution of foundational questions in quantum mechanics, such as the measurement problem or the emergence of classicality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Probably she meant to say “coupling” instead of “commuting.”

  2. In Sect. 2.1 of [5] Crull briefly discusses the role measurements play in quantum mechanics, but by doing so she only contributes to a long tradition of fallacious statements regarding the issue. She tries to define a measurement entity as something capable of gaining information about some system, such that the information can later be gathered. However, such definition is so vague that it is practically useless. Moreover, it is circular because in order to gather such information at a later time one, presumably, needs to somehow measure it!

  3. For any operator A, its trace is defined by \(Tr(A)=\sum _i \langle \phi _i|A|\phi _i\rangle \) with \(\{\phi _i\}\) any basis of the Hilbert space in question.

  4. In [5], the basis problem is associated with the following question: “Given the statistical improbability of always observing bases that are classical, why should such preferences for them appear in nature?” We find the decision to state the problem in terms of a statistical improbability quite curious since one does not expect the observed basis to be chosen at random.

  5. Given that the particular interpretation we consider in [2] is fundamentally indeterministic, we find it odd for Crull to claim that the urgency to consider a specific interpretation most often arises from a hesitation to accept that the world is indeterministic.

  6. Apparently, Crull finds our brief review of basic features of objective collapse models in [2], which she takes to be a definition of such models, unsatisfactory: “one might argue that the way in which [Okon and Sudarsky] define objective collapse theories introduces as many black boxes as it purports to explain.” It is unclear what is it that she finds in need of further explanation. Evidently, if one is looking for a completely viable collapse model compatible with relativistic quantum field theory, one will not find it in our work, nor elsewhere, since such a theory is still very much under construction. Therefore, one should not compare it directly with finished proposals, such as “decoherence” or the “Consistent Histories” approach. That is, one cannot compare directly programs under development, such as quantum gravity proposals, with well established theories such as general relativity, and demand the former to be as precisely formulated at this stage as is the latter. On the other hand, one must recognize the potential of the former to deal with evident shortcomings of the latter (i.e., the incompatibility of GR with quantum theory). At any rate, the literature on objective collapse models is of course large and of excellent quality (see e.g., [4] and references therein).

  7. It is worth mentioning that J. Hartle long ago noted the serious difficulties faced in attempting to apply quantum theory to cosmology, [20]. This lead him and his collaborators to conclude that some modified version of quantum theory was required. They turned to the Consistent Histories framework, about which we will say more later.

  8. Things get further complicated by the fact that these constructions turn out to be inequivalent. However, a careful analysis using the algebraic approach shows that these problems can be readily overcome [27].

  9. Strictly speaking, if the expansion of the universe is not exactly exponential, and the space-time is therefore not truly described by the de Sitter line element, the state is not the Bunch–Davies vacuum. However, the important point for our purposes is that in such scenario the vacuum is still homogeneous and isotropic.

  10. The simplicity of the structure of the previous argument can be illustrated with the following straightforward example: Suppose that we have a classical system, as complicated as you like, but such that, at \(t=0\), its total energy is zero. Suppose, moreover, that the Hamiltonian of the system is time-translation invariant. As a result, the total energy of the system, at any other time, and independently of the details of the evolution, will also be zero. The same is true of the symmetry of the Bunch–Davies state under standard evolution.

References

  1. Bell, J.S.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Okon, E., Sudarsky, D.: Benefits of objective collapse models for cosmology and quantum gravity. Found. Phys. 44, 114–143 (2014)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Goldstein, S.: “Bohmian Mechanics,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)

  4. Ghirardi, G.C.: “Collapse Theories,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)

  5. Crull, E.M.: Less interpretation and more decoherence in quantum gravity and inflationary cosmology. Found. Phys. 45, 1019–1045 (2015)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Schlosshauer, M.: Decoherence and the Quantum-to-Classical Transition. Springer, Berlin (2008)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Zurek, W.H.: “Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical - Revisited,” Updated version, available at arXiv:quant-ph/0306072, of W. H. Zurek, “Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical,” Phys. Today 44(10), 3644 (1991)

  8. Dirac, P.A.M.: The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1930)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. von Newmann, J.: Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. Springer, Berlin (1932)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777 (1935)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. d’Espagnat, B.: Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edn. Addison Wesley, Reading (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Aspect, A., Grangier, P., Roger, G.: Experimental tests of realistic local theories via Bell’s theorem. Phys. Rev. Lett. 47, 460 (1981)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  13. Aspect, A., Grangier, P., Roger, G.: Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Aspect, A., Dalibard, J., Roger, G.: Experimental realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm Gedankenexperiment: a new violation of Bell’s inequalities. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804 (1982)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Bell, J.S.: On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1(3), 195–200 (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Pearle, P.: Combining stochastic dynamical state-vector reduction with spontaneous localization. Phys. Rev. A 39, 2277–2289 (1989)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  17. Ghirardi, G.C., Rimini, A., Weber, T.: Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys. Rev. D 34, 470–491 (1986)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Tumulka, R.: A relativistic version of the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber model. J. Stat. Phys. 125, 821–840 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Bedingham, D.: Relativistic state reduction model. J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 306, 1–7 (2011)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Hartle, J.B.: Generalizing quantum mechanics for quantum gravity. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 45, 1390–1396 (2006)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Perez, A., Sahlmman, H., Sudarsky, D.: On the quantum mechanical origin of the seeds of cosmic structure. Class. Quantum Gravity 23, 2317 (2006). arXiv:gr-qc/0508100

  22. Landau, S.J., Scoccola, C.G., Sudarsky, D.: Cosmological constraints on nonstandard inflationary quantum collapse models. Phys. Rev. D 85, 123001 (2012). arXiv:1112.1830 [astro-ph.CO]

  23. Cañate, P., Pearl, P., Sudarsky, D.: CSL quantum origin of the primordial fluctuation. Phys. Rev. D 87, 104024 (2013). arXiv:1211.3463 [gr-qc]

  24. León García, G., Landau, S.J., Sudarsky, D.: Quantum origin of the primordial fluctuation spectrum and its statistics. Phys. Rev. D 88, 023526 (2013). arXiv:1107.3054 [astro-ph.CO]

  25. Penrose, R.: The Road to Reality. Alfred A. Knopf, New York (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Hawking, S.: Quantum black holes. In: Hawking, S., Penrose, R. (eds.) The Nature of Space and Time, pp. 37–60. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Wald, R.M.: Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime and Black Hole Thermodynamics (Chicago Lectures in Physics). University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1994)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Kiefer, C., Polarski, D.: Why do cosmological perturbations look classical to us? Adv. Sci. Lett. 2(2), 164–173 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Sudarsky, D.: Shortcomings in the understanding of why cosmological perturbations look classical. Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 20, 509 (2011). arXiv:0906.0315 [gr-qc]

  30. Castagnino, M., Fortin, S., Laura, R., Sudarsky, D.: Interpretations of quantum theory in the light of modern cosmology. arXiv:1412.7576 [gr-qc] (2014)

  31. Gambini, R., Porto, R.A., Pullin, J.: Realistic clocks, universal decoherence and the black hole information paradox. Phys. Rev. Lett. 93, 240401 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  32. Gambini, R., Porto, R.A., Pullin, J.: A relational solution to the problem of time in quantum mechanics and quantum gravity: a fundamental mechanism for quantum decoherence. New J. Phys. 6, 45 (2004)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  33. Butterfield, J.: Assessing the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 52, 75 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Zurek, W.H.: Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical. Rev. Mod. Phys. 75(3), 715 (2003). arXiv:quant-ph/0105127

  35. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.: Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison Wesley, Redwood City (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.: Classical equations for quantum systems. Phys. Rev. D 47, 3345 (1993)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Dowker, F., Kent, A.: On the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics. J. Stat. Phys. 82, 1575–1646 (1996)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  39. Okon, E., Sudarsky, D.: On the consistency of the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 44, 19–33 (2014)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. Okon, E., Sudarsky, D.: The consistent histories formalism and the measurement problem. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 52, 217–222 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. Saunders, S., et al. (eds.): Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory, and Reality. Oxford University Press (2010)

Download references

Acknowledgments

We acknowledge partial financial support from DGAPA-UNAM Project IG100316.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elias Okon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Okon, E., Sudarsky, D. Less Decoherence and More Coherence in Quantum Gravity, Inflationary Cosmology and Elsewhere. Found Phys 46, 852–879 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-016-0007-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-016-0007-x

Keywords

Navigation