Skip to main content
Log in

Will the Real Moral Judgment Please Stand Up?

The Implications of Social Intuitionist Models of Cognition for Meta-ethics and Moral Psychology

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The recent, influential Social Intuitionist Model of moral judgment (Haidt, Psychological Review 108, 814–834, 2001) proposes a primary role for fast, automatic and affectively charged moral intuitions in the formation of moral judgments. Haidt’s research challenges our normative conception of ourselves as agents capable of grasping and responding to reasons. We argue that there can be no ‘real’ moral judgments in the absence of a capacity for reflective shaping and endorsement of moral judgments. However, we suggest that the empirical literature indicates a complex interplay between automatic and deliberative mental processes in moral judgment formation, with the latter constraining the expression and influence of moral intuitions. We therefore conclude that the psychological literature supports a normative conception of agency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We acknowledge that talk about ‘our’ concept of moral judgment is ambiguous between the concept actually held by the folk or a version that refines and systematises elements of the folk concept. Perhaps we could test the first empirically by doing a survey but we think it unlikely that this will deliver a clear answer. The accounts we favour do the second. As one of us has argued elsewhere (Kennett 2006) we think the concept that makes best sense of moral practices which are universal—of offering justifications, excuses, and of holding responsible—is expressed in the platitude that moral requirements have the status of reasons.

  2. We set aside a number of concerns about the dumbfounding experiments and Haidt’s interpretation of the results here but see Kasachkoff and Saltzstein (2008) and Kennett (forthcoming).

  3. Haidt might not agree that his theory is emotivist but we think that his interpretation of public moral ‘reasoning’ as a process by which exposure to the responses of others may evoke new intuitions in us as clearly consistent with the emotivist claim that a function of moral judgment is to influence the feelings of others. Haidt has argued against charges of emotivism, noting that the moral intuitions on which moral judgments are thought to be based are not purely affective (Haidt and Bjorkland 2007b). However, our understanding of the SIM is that the moral judgment is based largely on the affective, evaluative component of the intuition.

  4. Hierarchical views like Frankfurt’s have been criticised on a number of grounds. It is not immediately clear, for example, that second order desires need be a product of reflection—they might just happen to us—or that reflection will issue in second order, rather than first order desires. Frankfurt however clearly takes reflection be essential to personhood. He says “ it is only in virtue of his rational capacities that a person is capable of becoming critically aware of his own will” (pp. 11–12). It is critical reflection on his desires that constitutes him as a person rather than a wanton. If this is right then a mere hierarchy of cognitive states will not do the trick. Controlled processes which take as their subject the question of where the agent herself should stand on a particular issue will be required.

  5. Jones (2003, p.194) argues persuasively that “the commitment to rational guidance is the commitment to the on-going cultivation and exercise of whatever abilities it is that enable the agent to have and display the capacities that are characteristic of reason-responders.” She thinks that these capacities will include various kinds of emotional responsiveness. In this respect we interpret her as providing an account of ideal rational agency.

  6. Psychopaths are also deficient in self-regulatory capacities but unlike Haidt we think these capacities require the kind of reflective self-awareness that is central to rationalist and sophisticated sentimentalist accounts.

  7. For more detailed arguments supporting this general conclusion see Fine and Kennett (2004), Kennett (2002, 2006) and Kennett and Matthews (2007).

  8. Their impairments in empathy differ from those of the psychopath. Blair (1996) has shown that autistic children are somewhat sensitive to others’ distress (emotional empathy) even though they have great difficulty with perspective taking (cognitive empathy). In addition, recent research with adult populations with Asperger’s syndrome finds that although they are impaired in cognitive empathy, they score similarly to neurotypical controls on measures of emotional empathy (Dziobek et al. 2008; Rogers et al. 2007).

  9. This example also cited in Kennett (2002).

  10. We are not suggesting here that intuition plays no role whatsoever in the process of moral reasoning in the case of autistic individuals. Perhaps Sinclair’s initial realisation that he should do something was in the nature of an intuition. But in this case it is plain that there is a reliance on explicit controlled processes in order to resolve a puzzle and reach a practical conclusion about what ought to be done. Moreover the process of reflection is reflexive, it does involve taking oneself to be responsive to reasons and Sinclair sees his efforts in this light.

  11. We believe this is consistent with the view held by Jones and also argued for in Bennett (1974) and Kennett (2001) that conflict between sympathy and considered judgments should sometimes prompt a reconsideration of the judgments themselves since we are not omniscient about value and our sympathies are often (though not infallibly) reason tracking. Such reconsiderations are part and parcel of ideal reasons responsiveness. Huck Finn clearly fell short of this ideal in making his moral judgments, nevertheless it seems reasonable to assume that his ‘real’ moral judgments were the judgments for which he could provide an explicit (though no doubt flawed) justification and with respect to which he regarded himself as weak.

  12. While it might be argued that such correction requires external promptings rarely found outside the laboratory we would disagree. We do often draw each other’s attention to mood as influencing our judgments and we often correct for mood unprompted. It is not uncommon for people to explain judgments and actions which they reflectively disavow in terms of the contaminating effects of emotion etc. “I was too angry (tired, upset, down, excited). I didn’t mean it”.

  13. The study found complex and somewhat unexpected interactions between private versus public setting, motivation to control prejudiced responses, and implicit attitudes.

References

  • Amodio DM, Devine PG, Harman E (2008) Individual differences in the regulation of intergroup bias: the role of conflict monitoring and neural signals for control. J Pers Soc Psychol 94:60–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer AJ (1936) Language, truth, and logic (2nd edn). Gollancz, London (1946)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh J, Chartrand TL (1999) The unbearable automaticity of being. Am Psychol 54:462–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh J, Ferguson MJ (2000) Beyond behaviourism: on the automaticity of higher mental processes. Psychol Bull 126:925–945

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Williams EL (2006) The automaticity of social life. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 15:1–4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Gollwitzer PM, Lee-Chai A, Barndollar K, Trötschel R (2001) The automated will: nonconscious activation and pursuit of behavioral goals. J Pers Soc Psychol 81:1014–1027

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett LF, Tugade MM, Engle RW (2004) Individual differences in working memory capacity and dual-process theories of mind. Psychol Bull 130:553–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett J (1974) The conscience of Huckleberry Finn. Philosophy 49:123–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJR (1996) Brief report: morality in the autistic child. J Autism Dev Disord 26:571–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deigh J (1995) Empathy and universalizability. Ethics 105:743–763

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dovidio JF, Kawakami K, Johnson C, Johnson B, Howard A (1997) On the nature of prejudice: automatic and controlled components. J Exp Soc Psychol 33:510–540

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duckworth KL, Bargh JA, Garcia M, Chaiken S (2002) The automatic evaluation of novel stimuli. Psychol Sci 13:513–519

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dziobek I, Rogers K, Fleck S, Bahnemann M, Heekeren HR, Wolf OT, Convit A (2008) Dissociation of cognitive and emotional empathy in adults with asperger syndrome using the multifaceted empathy test (MET). J Autism Dev Disord 38:464–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eyssel F, Bohner G (2007) The rating of sexist humor under time pressure as an indicator of spontaneous sexist attitudes. Sex Roles 57:651–660

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazio RH (1990) Multiple processes by which attitudes guide behaviour: The MODE model as an integrative framework. In: Zanna MP (ed) Advances in experimental social psychology, vol 23. Academic, San Diego, pp 75–109

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fazio RH (2001) On the automatic activation of associated evaluations: an overview. Cogn Emot 15:115–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazio RH, Olson MA (2003) Implicit measures in social cognition research: their meaning and use. Annu Rev Psychol 54:297–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine C (2006) Is the emotional dog wagging its rational tail, or chasing it? Philos Explor 9:83–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine C, Kennett J (2004) Mental impairment, moral understanding and criminal responsibility: psychopathy and the purposes of punishment. Int J Law Psychiatry 27:425–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forgas JP, Moylan SJ (1987) After the movies: the effects of transient mood states on social judgments. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 13:478–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt H (1971) Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. J Philos 68:5–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel U, Banse R, Hug F (2007) Predicting private and public helping behaviour by implicit attitudes and the motivation to control prejudiced reactions. Br J Soc Psychol 46:365–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gawronski B, Hofmann W, Wilbur CJ (2006) Are “implicit” attitudes unconscious? Conscious Cogn 15:485–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaser J, Kihlstrom JF (2005) Compensatory automaticity: Unconscious volition is not an oxymoron. In: Hassin RR, Uleman JS, Bargh JA (eds) The new unconscious. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 171–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Govorun O, Payne BK (2006) Ego depletion and prejudice: separating automatic and controlled components. Social Cogn 24:111–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald AG, McGhee DE, Schwartz JKL (1998) Measuring individual differences in implicit cognition: the implicit association test. J Pers Soc Psychol 74:1464–1480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald AG, Nosek BA, Banaji MR (2003) Understanding and using the implicit association test I: an improved scoring algorithm. J Pers Soc Psychol 85:197–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald AG, Krieger LH (2006) Implicit bias: scientific foundations. Calif Law Rev 94:945–967

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108:814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2007) The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science 316:998–1002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Bjorkland F (2007a) Social intuitionists answer six questions about moral psychology. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology, volume 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. MIT, Boston, pp 181–218

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Bjorkland F (2007b) Social intuitionists reason, in conversation. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology, volume 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. MIT, Boston, pp 241–254

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Hersh MA (2001) Sexual morality: the cultures and emotions of conservatives and liberals. J Appl Soc Psychol 31:191–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann W, Gschwendner T, Nosek BA, Schmitt M (2005) What moderates implicit-explicit consistency? Eur Rev Soc Psychol 16:335–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann W, Rauch W, Gawronski B (2007). And deplete us not into temptation: automatic attitudes, dietary restraint, and self-regulatory resources as determinants of eating behavior. J Exp Soc Psychol 43:497–504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones K (2003) Emotion, weakness of will and the normative conception of agency. In: Hatzimoysis A (ed) Philosophy and the Emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 181–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasachkoff T, Saltzstein HD (2008) Reasoning and moral decision making: a critique of the social intuitionist model. EJDS 2:287–302

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (2001) Agency and responsibility: A common-sense moral psychology. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (2002) Autism, empathy and moral agency. Philos Q 52:340–357

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (2006) ‘Do psychopaths really threaten moral rationalism?’. Philos Explor 9:69–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J, Matthews S (2007) Normative agency. In: Atkins K, MacKenzie C (eds) Practical Identity and Narrative Agency. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (forthcoming) Living with one’s choices: moral reasoning in vivo and in vitro

  • Kiefer AK, Sanchez DT (2007) Men’s sex-dominance inhibition: do men automatically refrain from sexually dominant behavior? Pers Soc Psychol Bull 33:1617–1631

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard CM (2002) Self-constitution: agency, identity, and integrity. The Locke lectures available at http://www.people.fas.harvard.edu/~korsgaar/

  • Kunda Z, Spencer SJ (2003) When do stereotypes come to mind and when do they color judgment? A goal-based theoretical framework for stereotype activation and application. Psychol Bull 129:522–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore L, Brown R (1997) Category and stereotype activation: is prejudice inevitable? J Pers Soc Psychol 72:275–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lerner JS, Goldberg JH, Tetlock PE (1998) Sober second thought: the effects of accountability, anger, and authoritarianism on attributions of responsibility. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 24:563–574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddux WW, Barden J, Brewer MB, Petty RE (2005) Saying no to negativity: the effects of context and motivation to control prejudice on automatic evaluative responses. J Exp Soc Psychol 41:19–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monteith MJ, Voils CI (1998) Proneness to prejudiced responses: toward understanding the authenticity of self-reported discrepancies. J Pers Soc Psychol 75:901–916

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monteith MJ, Ashburn-Nardo L, Voils CI, Czopp AM (2002) Putting the brakes on prejudice: on the development and operation of cues for control. J Pers Soc Psychol 83:1029–1050

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moskowitz GB, Gollwitzer PM, Wasel W, Schaal B (1999) Preconscious control of stereotype activation through chronic egalitarian goals. J Pers Soc Psychol 77:167–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nosek BA (2007) Implicit-explicit relations. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 16:65–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne BK (2001) Prejudice and perception: the role of automatic and controlled processes in misperceiving a weapon. J Pers Soc Psychol 81:181–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne K (2005) Conceptualizing control in social cognition: how executive functioning modulates the expression of automatic stereotyping. J Pers Soc Psychol 89:488–503

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne BK, Cheng CM, Govorun O, Stewart BD (2005a) An inkblot for attitudes: affect misattribution as implicit measurement. J Pers Soc Psychol 89:277–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne B, Jacoby LL, Lambert AJ (2005b) Attitudes as accessibility bias: Dissociating automatic and controlled processes. In: Hassin RR, Uleman JS, Bargh JA (eds) The New Unconscious. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 393–420

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2006) The emotional basis of moral judgments. Philos Explor 9:29–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachels J (1993) Subjectivism. In: Singer P (ed) A Companion to ethics. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 432–441

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers K, Dziobek I, Hassenstab J, Wolf OT, Convit A (2007) Who cares? Revisiting empathy in asperger syndrome. J Autism Dev Disord 37:709–715

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rydell RJ, McConnell AR (2006) Understanding implicit and explicit attitude change: a systems of reasoning analysis. J Pers Soc Psychol 91:995–1008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saltzstein HD, Kasachkoff T (2004) Haidt’s moral intuitionist theory: a psychological and philosophical critique. Rev Gen Psychol 8:273–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz N, Clore GL (1983) Mood, misattribution, and judgments of well-being: informative and directive functions of affective states. J Pers Soc Psychol 45:513–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman JW, Gawronsko B, Gonsalkorale K, Hugenberg K, Allen TJ, Groom CJ (2008) The self-regulation of automatic associations and behavioral impulses. Psychol Rev 115:314–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair J (1992) Bridging the gaps: An inside-out view of autism (or, do you know what I don’t know?). In: Schopler E, Mesibov GB (eds) High-functioning individuals with autism. Plenum, New York, pp 294–302

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1987) The Humean theory of motivation. Mind 96:36–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1994) The moral problem. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith ER, DeCoster J (2000) Dual-process models in social and cognitive psychology: conceptual integration and links to underlying memory systems. Pers Soc Psychol Rev 4:108–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson CL (1937) The emotive meaning of ethical terms. Mind, 46:14–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strack F, Deutsch R (2004) Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behaviour. Pers Soc Psychol Rev 8:220–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart BD, Payne BK (2008) Bringing automatic stereotyping under control: implementation intentions as efficient means of thought control. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 34:1332–1345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman JD (2000) The possibility of practical reason. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace RJ (1999) Moral cognitivism and motivation. Philos Rev 108(2):161–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson G (1982) Free agency. In: Watson G (ed) Free will, 1st edition. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 96–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegener DT, Petty RE (1995) Flexible correction processes in social judgment: the role of naïve theories in corrections for perceived bias. J Pers Soc Psychol 68:36–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley T, Haidt J (2005) Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychol Sci 16:780–784

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson TD, Brekke N (1994) Mental contamination and mental correction: unwanted influences on judgments and evaluations. Psychol Bull 116:117–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods M (1972) Reasons for action and desires. Suppl proc Aristot Soc 46:189–201

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank Neil Levy, Edward Hare, and audiences at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference 2007, Monash University, Radboud University and the University of Oxford for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. The authors acknowledge the support of the Australian Research Council for this project. We thank audiences at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference 2007 and at Monash University, Radboud University, and the University of Oxford for stimulating and helpful discussions. We owe particular thanks to Neil Levy and an anonymous referee for forcing us to clarify our argument at a number of points.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeanette Kennett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kennett, J., Fine, C. Will the Real Moral Judgment Please Stand Up?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 12, 77–96 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-008-9136-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-008-9136-4

Keywords

Navigation