1 Introduction

Self-locating beliefs—namely, those beliefs that situate an agent at a location or a time—are commonplace. You acquire a self-locating belief whenever you come to learn of the time by glancing at your watch or if you learn of your location by observing a street sign. The converse situation can also arise, in which you may be initially certain about some self-locating belief (such as the time) but then you gain a new piece of evidence (that your watch is broken), rendering you uncertain about the self-locating belief [Bradley (2007)]. More generally, the question arises as to how one should distribute one’s credence over self-locating beliefs about which one is uncertain.

In Defeating Dr. Evil with Self-Locating Belief, Elga (2004) defends a response to this question. The response amounts to a version of the principle of indifference—where, under specified circumstances, one should spread one’s credence equally over the various hypotheses. More specifically, the version of the principle of indifference that Elga defends is as follows:

Indifference: Similar centered worlds deserve equal credence (Elga, 2004, p. 387).

A centered world is a possible world with a designated individual and a designated time. It can be specified as a triple (wit), where w is a possible world, i is some individual in w, and t is a time. Similar centered worlds satisfy two conditions: (i) they agree on the first argument of the triple (but not necessarily on the latter two); (ii) the individuals that exist in each centered world are in subjectively indistinguishable states.Footnote 1 Note that while principles of indifference have been extensively discussed, the formulation in Elga (2004) has been particularly influential.Footnote 2

In justifying Indifference, Elga considers a sequence of three (related) thought experiments: Duplication, Toss &Duplication, and Coma. We claim that Elga’s analysis of the Coma scenario is flawed, relying on an assertion which can be justified only by assuming the truth of the proposition that he is trying to demonstrate. We are not disputing the claim that Indifference is reasonable—indeed, in an upcoming paper we will make use of such a principle in assessing certain cosmological theories. Our remarks here target only the justification that Elga provides for Indifference. For us, Indifference is a principle that one can reasonably adopt, based on some sort of appeal to the absence of any reason to assign unequal credences, but not based on any determinative calculation of the sort presented by Elga.Footnote 3

Our plan for this paper is as follows. In Sect. 2 we summarize Elga’s thought experiments, and describe our claim that the analysis of Coma is flawed. Sect. 3 describes a Bayesian calculation that shows in detail how we believe the Coma scenario should be analyzed. We summarize our argument in Sect. 4. In an appendix, we reexamine step-by-step a crucial footnote from Elga’s paper, showing how the conclusions found there are modified by our analysis of Coma.

2 Reanalysis of Elga’s Thought Experiments

Elga’s first thought experiment describes two similar centered worlds in which a person named “Al” is duplicated. The experiment is described as follows.

Duplication: After Al goes to sleep researchers create a duplicate of him in a duplicate environment. The next morning, Al and the duplicate awaken in subjectively indistinguishable states (Elga, 2004, p. 388).

The issue at stake is how Al should distribute his credence between the hypothesis that he is Al and the hypothesis that he is the duplicate. In order to justify why Al should distribute his credence evenly between the two hypotheses (which is indeed what would be implied by Indifference), Elga introduces two further experiments: Toss &Duplication and Coma (the latter will be described shortly).

Toss &Duplication: After Al goes to sleep, researchers toss a coin that has a 10% chance of landing heads. Then (regardless of the toss outcome) they duplicate Al. The next morning, Al and the duplicate awaken in subjectively indistinguishable states (Elga, 2004, p. 388).

In our discussion we will generalize the chance of the coin landing heads from the specified value of 10% to an arbitrary \(P_0(H)\), assuming only that \(P_0(H)\) is not equal to 0 or 1. Elga claims (and we agree) that

...Al’s state of opinion (when he awakens) as to whether he is Al or the duplicate ought to be the same in Toss &Duplication as it is in Duplication. So in order to show that in Duplication, Al ought to divide his credence evenly between the hypothesis that he is Al and the hypothesis that he is the duplicate, it is enough to show that he ought to do so in Toss &Duplication (Elga, 2004, pp. 388–389).

To show that Al ought to divide his credence evenly between the hypothesis that he is Al and that he is the duplicate (in Toss &Duplication), Elga states three claims, which we (re)describe here. Following Elga (2004) and Weatherson (2005), we will use the following abbreviations:

$$\begin{aligned} H:&\text { the coin lands `heads'}; \\ T:&\text { the coin lands `tails'}; \\ A:&\text { I am Al}; \\ D:&\text { I am Dup (Al's duplicate)}. \end{aligned}$$

The credence function that Al ought to have immediately upon awakening will be denoted by \(P(\cdot )\). Elga’s three claims can be stated as follows:

  1. (C1)

    Al’s credence in H ought to be equal to the chance of the coin landing heads:

    $$\begin{aligned} P(H)=P_0(H). \end{aligned}$$
    (1)
  2. (C2)

    Al’s credence in H, given ((H and A) or (T and A)), ought to be equal to his credence in H:

    $$\begin{aligned} P(H | HA \hbox { or } TA) = P_0 (H). \end{aligned}$$
    (2)
  3. (C3)

    Al’s credence in H, given ((H and A) or (T and D)), ought to be equal to his credence in H:

    $$\begin{aligned} P(H | HA \hbox { or } TD) = P_0(H). \end{aligned}$$
    (3)

Claim (C3) (which Elga indeed deems to be controversial) is established by considering another thought experiment, viz. Coma.

Coma: As in Toss &Duplication, the experimenters toss a coin and duplicate Al. But the following morning, the experimenters ensure that only one person wakes up: If the coin lands heads, they allow Al to wake up (and put the duplicate into a coma); if the coin lands tails, they allow the duplicate to wake up (and put Al into a coma) (Elga, 2004, pp. 390–391).

Elga then claims (a claim with which we agree) that one can determine the value of the left-hand side of Eq. (3) by considering what Al’s credence in H should be in Coma. That is, when Al awakens in Coma, were he to indeed awaken, his situation would be exactly as it would have been in Toss &Duplication, but then updated by the new information \((HA \hbox { or } TD)\). Thus, Al’s credence function in Coma, if he awakens, ought to be given by

$$\begin{aligned} P_{\textsc {Coma}}(\cdot ) = P(\cdot |HA \hbox { or } TD). \end{aligned}$$
(4)

In particular,

$$\begin{aligned} P_{\textsc {Coma}}(H) = P(H|HA \hbox { or } TD). \end{aligned}$$
(5)

Al’s credence in H in Coma is ascertained, by Elga, using the following argument (on p. 392)Footnote 4:

Before Al was put to sleep, he was sure that the chance of the coin landing heads was \(P_0(H)\), and his credence in H should have accorded with this chance: it too should have been \(P_0(H)\). When he wakes up, his epistemic situation with respect to the coin is just the same as it was before he went to sleep. He has neither gained nor lost information relevant to the toss outcome. So his degree of belief in H should continue to accord with the chance of H at the time of the toss. In other words, his degree of belief in H should continue to be \(P_0(H)\).

In short, Elga’s claim is that in Coma, if Al awakens, he ought to continue to set his credence in the coin landing heads to the known chance of heads, \(P_0(H)\).

Given claims (C1), (C2), and (C3), Elga (correctly) concludes that \(P(A)=P(D)=1/2\) in Toss &Duplication and thus (by the reasoning described above) in Duplication. We, however, take issue with the justification provided for claim (C3).

From our point of view, Elga appears to be using circular reasoning in (C3), where he claims that Al’s credence in H should remain equal to \(P_0(H)\) when he awakens in Coma. In particular, it is not the case that when Al wakes up “his epistemic situation with respect to the coin toss is just the same as it was before he went to sleep. He has neither gained nor lost information relevant to the toss outcome.” We contend that Al has both gained and lost information relevant to the toss outcome:

  1. (i)

    He has lost information as regards his identity: before Al went to sleep he was sure that he was Al; after he awakens, the possibility arises that he is Dup. No amount of introspection (or an inspection of his external environment) can reveal to him whether he is Al or Dup. (This is what we take to be the meaning of the assumption that Al and Dup would be in “subjectively indistinguishable” states.)

  2. (ii)

    He has gained the information that he is now in a predicament in which his identity (again, about which he is now unsure) is perfectly correlated with the toss outcome.

Al’s uncertainty about his identity [as described in (i)] is directly relevant to his belief about the toss outcome [as described in (ii)].

In particular, when Al awakens in Toss &Duplication, he has no way of knowing if he is Al or Dup. If he adopts Indifference, he will conclude that he should give equal credence to each possibility. However, since Elga is trying to demonstrate Indifference, circularity can be avoided only if we allow Al to adopt an initial credence that is not equal to 1/2. Hence we set P(A), Al’s credence that he is Al upon awakening in Toss &Duplication, equal to some arbitrary ‘prior’ credence \(Pr_A\), which Al is free to choose.Footnote 5

In Coma, as discussed just above Eq. (4), Al (if and when he awakens) begins with the same credences as in Toss &Duplication, which are then updated by the new information (\(HA \hbox { or } TD\)). The role of \(Pr_A\) is important, because if \(Pr_A\) is not equal to 1/2, then clearly Al’s credence in H is affected by the new information. For example, if \(Pr_A\) is nearly one, then his credence in H should obviously increase on awakening in Coma, since if he is Al, then the coin must have landed heads. This issue is well-described by a standard Bayesian analysis, which we give in the next section. We will see that Al’s credence in H upon awakening in Coma should remain \(P_0(H)\) if and only if Al assumes that \(Pr_A= 1/2\). This means that Elga’s conclusion is valid if and only if one assumes Indifference from the start.Footnote 6

3 A Bayesian Approach

In this section we apply Bayes’ theorem to determine how Al should update his credence in H, using the new information, (\(HA \hbox { or } TD\)), that he acquires on awakening in the Coma scenario. To determine how Al should update his credence in H, we will compute the right-hand side of Eq. (5), recalling that \(P(\cdot )\) is the credence function in Toss &Duplication.

Our derivation will make use of the fact that in Toss &Duplication the H/T choice is independent of the A/D choice, which follows as a consequence of claim (C2) (with which we do not take issue). This independence follows from the same words that Elga uses to justify claim (C2): “So Al should count the toss outcome as irrelevant to who he is” (Elga, 2004, p. 389). Formally, the independence of H and A can be derived from claim (C2) by noting that \((H \text { or } T)\) is true, so \(P(H | HA \hbox { or } TA) = P(H | A)\), and therefore (C2) implies that \(P(H | A) = P_0(H)\). This is of course a way of stating that A and H are independent. Using Bayes’ theorem, this statement is equivalent to \(P(A|H) = Pr_A\).

Recalling that \(P(H) = P_0(H)\) is the initially specified chance that the coin landed heads, Bayes’ theorem can be used to rewrite the right-hand side of Eq. (5) as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} P(H | HA\hbox { or } TD)&=\frac{P(HA \hbox { or } TD|H)}{P(HA \hbox { or } TD)}P_0(H) \end{aligned}$$
(6a)
$$\begin{aligned}&=\frac{P(A|H)}{P(HA)+P(TD)}P_0(H) \end{aligned}$$
(6b)
$$\begin{aligned}&=\frac{Pr_A}{P_0(H){Pr_A}+P_0(T)Pr_D}P_0(H) \end{aligned}$$
(6c)
$$\begin{aligned}&\equiv F \, P_0(H), \end{aligned}$$
(6d)

where \(Pr_D\equiv 1-Pr_A\) is Al’s prior credence in Toss &Duplication that he is Dup, and

$$\begin{aligned} F \equiv \frac{Pr_A}{P_0(H) {Pr_A} + P_0(T) Pr_D}. \end{aligned}$$
(7)

In Eq. (6c) we have used the independence of H and A (and that of T and D). As we claimed at the end of the previous section, Al’s credence in H after awakening in Coma, which is equal to \(P(H | HA \hbox { or } TD)\), remains equal to \(P_0(H)\) only if \(F=1\). By rewriting F as

$$\begin{aligned} F = \dfrac{1}{1 + \dfrac{P_0(T)}{Pr_A} \bigl [{Pr_D} - {Pr_A}\bigr ]}, \end{aligned}$$
(8)

one can easily see that \(F=1\) only if the prior credences \({Pr_A}\) and \({Pr_D}\) (which must sum to 1) are each taken to be 1/2.Footnote 7

Thus, taking into account the implications of Bayes’ theorem, claim (C3) should be modified to a new claim, which we will denote by (C\(3^{\prime }\)):

(\(\hbox {C}3^{\prime }\)):

Al’s credence in H if he awakens in Coma, \(P_{\textsc {Coma}}(H)\), which is equal to \(P(H | HA \hbox { or } TD)\), ought to be equal to the product of F [given in Eq. (7)] and his credence in heads \(P(H)=P_0(H)\) as he awakens, before he updates his credences with the new information (\(HA \hbox { or } TD\)):

$$\begin{aligned} P_{\textsc {Coma}}(H) = P(H | HA \hbox { or } TD) = F \, P_0(H). \end{aligned}$$
(9)

Note that (C\(3^{\prime }\)) agrees with (C3) only if \({Pr_A}\) is assumed to be 1/2.

In his footnote 8, Elga uses claims (C1), (C2), and (C3) to show that \(P(A)=P(D)\), which completes his demonstration that Indifference is true for this situation. (In an appendix, he generalizes the argument to defend arbitrary instances of Indifference.) Since we have argued that (C3) should be replaced by (C\(3^{\prime }\)), the conclusion will of course be altered. In deriving Eq. (9), we calculated \(P(H | HA \hbox { or } TD)\), and hence F [see Eqs. (6) and (7)], assuming that \({Pr_A}\) and \(P_0(H)\) were given. We could imagine, however, that we were given the values of F and \(P_0(H)\), and were asked to infer the value of P(A), Al’s credence in being Al when he awakens in Toss &Duplication. Equation (7) would still hold [replacing \(Pr_A\) and \(Pr_D\) by generic quantities P(A) and P(D)], so we could then find P(A) directly from Eq. (7), recalling that \(P(D) = 1 - P(A)\) and \(P_0(T) = 1 - P_0(H)\). The result would be

$$\begin{aligned} P_{{\mathrm {inferred}}}(A) =\dfrac{F P_0(T)}{1 - F + 2 F P_0(T)}, \end{aligned}$$
(10)

where we use the special notation \(P_{{\mathrm {inferred}}}(A)\) to denote the value of P(A) that is inferred from assumptions (C1), (C2), and (C\(3^{\prime }\)). This calculation is a version of Elga’s derivation in footnote 8, which is shorter than Elga’s argument and allows an arbitrary value for F. We can see immediately that if we assume that \(F=1\), as in claim (C3), we recover Elga’s result that \(P_{{\mathrm {inferred}}}(A) = 1/2\). However, if we use the version of the claim based on Bayesian reasoning, namely (C\(3^{\prime }\)), we find instead [by substituting Eq. (7) into Eq. (10)] the trivial conclusion that

$$\begin{aligned} P_{{\mathrm {inferred}}}(A)={Pr_A}. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

That is, Al’s credence in being Al upon awakening in Toss &Duplication, as inferred by considering the experiment in Coma, is exactly equal to whatever prior credence \({Pr_A}\) that he assumed. Al will conclude that \(P_{{\mathrm {inferred}}}(A) = 1/2\) only if he assumed a prior credence \({Pr_A}\) equal to 1/2.

The argument above is an abbreviated version of Elga’s footnote 8, modified to use (C\(3^{\prime }\)) instead of (C3). In an appendix we show in detail that if the steps of Elga’s footnote 8 are followed exactly, but where F is introduced as in Eq. (9), we retrieve exactly the result of Eq. (10). Thus we see that once the circularity in Elga’s formulation is removed, the demonstration of the truth of Indifference disappears. Indifference can still be adopted as a reasonable principle, but Elga’s derivation of it is flawed.

4 Conclusion

Elga (2004) discusses a specific version of the principle of indifference, which applies to a situation where a possible world includes two or more individuals who, at some specified time for each of them, are in subjectively indistinguishable states. He illustrates this situation with an example called Duplication, in which someone named Al is duplicated while he sleeps, along with his environment, so that Al and his duplicate awaken in subjectively indistinguishable states. Through a sequence of three thought experiments, Elga argues that when Al awakens, he ought to assign equal credence to being the duplicate or to being Al.

In this paper we have argued that, while it is perfectly reasonable for Al to assume that he is equally likely to be the duplicate, he is not compelled to make this assumption. The reasoning that Elga used, we believe, is circular. Specifically, we differ in the analysis of the third thought experiment, called Coma, in which a coin with a 10% chance of landing heads is tossed while Al sleeps, and then the duplication takes place as before. If the coin lands heads, only Al is allowed to wake up, with the duplicate remaining in a coma; but if the coin lands tails, only the duplicate is allowed to wake up. Our disagreement centers on the credence that Al should have, when (and if) he awakens, in the coin having landed heads. Elga’s conclusions are based on the claim that Al’s credence in heads when he awakens should remain 10%. We argue, however, that this claim is true if and only if Al assumes that he is equally likely to be Al or the duplicate, which is exactly the conclusion that Elga is trying to demonstrate. If Al does not make this assumption, then he might, for example, assume that he is much more likely to be Al than the duplicate. In that case, his credence in heads should be increased upon learning that he has woken up. We carried out a Bayesian analysis of this thought experiment, and showed that Al may assume any prior credence in his being Al, and no inconsistencies arise.

As long as Al has no reason to believe that he is more likely to be either Al or the duplicate, then we agree that it is reasonable to quantify this absence of evidence by adopting the default proposition that he is equally likely to be either. Elga’s argument, however, did not rely on adopting a default proposition. Instead, Elga claimed to show directly from the descriptions of the thought experiments that Al could deduce that he should have equal credence in being Al or Dup. At the end of his argument, Elga proclaimed “So, Indifference is true.” Thus, Elga was arguing that Indifference is more than a reasonable proposition, but is instead a logically compelling conclusion. We maintain, however, that this argument is flawed.

In an email exchange with Adam Elga, he pointed out that circularity could be avoided by accepting (C3) as an “undefended premise in the argument.” To ensure the absence of circularity, it is important that (C3) has “independent appeal—credibility that does not derive from an antecedent commitment to Indifference.” We completely agree that if one does not provide support for (C3), but instead accepts it as a premise, then there is no circularity. For Elga, (C3) has appeal that is independent of Indifference. For us, however, (C3) has no such appeal; but there is no cause for debate, since the status of Elga’s argument turns on whether (C3) has such appeal, and we and Elga agree that there is no reason why intelligent folks should necessarily agree about the appeal of an undefended premise. Nevertheless, from our point of view, Elga’s original argument remains circular.