Skip to main content
Log in

The Collapse of Logical Pluralism has been Greatly Exaggerated

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to the logical pluralism of Beall and Restall, there are several distinct relations of logical consequence. Some critics argue that logical pluralism suffers from what I call the collapse problem: that despite its intention to articulate a radically pluralistic doctrine about logic, the view unintentionally collapses into logical monism. In this paper, I propose a contextualist resolution of the collapse problem. This clarifies the mechanism responsible for a plurality of logics and handles the motivating data better than the original view. It is a major improvement that should be embraced by all logical pluralists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. They sometimes refer to intuitionistic logic as constructive logic, but we will use its more familiar name.

  2. According to Carnap (1937), for example, we stipulate a logic when we construct a linguistic framework for our theory, allowing for a high degree of freedom about what can count as logic. Russell (2008) argues that there are different consequence relations over different classes of truth-bearers. Shapiro (2014a, b) has recently developed the view that logic is relative to mathematical structure and that some mathematical structures are intrinsically non-classical. Cook (2014) argues that anti-realists must accept an infinite number of equally good formal codifications of the relation of logical consequence. While each of these is aptly described as a form of logical pluralism, they are quite distinct from the view that concerns us in this paper.

  3. See Beall and Restall (2006, p. 89) for this formulation.

  4. They claim, furthermore, that this does not involve any equivocation with respect to the chosen terms. The ‘correctness’ of, e.g., relevant logic does not depend on attributing a different meaning to negation than that attributed by classical logic. See Beall and Restall (2006, pp. 97–98) and Restall (2002, 2014). I will revisit this topic in the objection and replies.

  5. See Wedgwood (2002, 2007) for related views of logic’s role in successful belief.

  6. See Beall and Restall (2006, p. 16) for this commitment. The next section elaborates on the place of normativity within the larger pluralist project.

  7. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me to think more about these issues of normativity.

  8. The class of possible worlds is a class of cases, but not all cases are possible worlds.

  9. For illuminating discussion of this literature, see Steinberger (2015).

  10. MacFarlane never considers the idea, taken up by Field (2009b, 2015), that the objects of logical norms are best construed as credal states (degrees of belief) rather than full belief (or disbelief). As such, all of the principles in MacFarlane’s taxonomy are qualitative rather than quantitative. I will only discuss qualitative formulations of logical norms in this paper because they are the only kind of norms considered by Harman, Beall and Restall, as well as the advocates of the collapse problem. Harman (1986, Chap. 3) actually argues that ordinary agents do not operate with degrees of belief. He considers the notion irrelevant to a theory of reasoning. Beall and Restall (2006, pp. 17–18) take the more conservative line that we often operate with full belief (and disbelief), hence if logic is normative for reasoning, it must pertain to these states.

  11. I always state single-premise formulations of such principles. Technically speaking, this principle Co\(+\) is a special case of MacFarlane’s original principle Co\(+\), which applies to multiple-premise argument forms. MacFarlane does not say anything about norms for multiple-conclusion argument forms, but his taxonomy could easily be extended to them as well. I focus on single-premise arguments because it makes things simpler and it is sufficient to bring out the most interesting skeptical challenges to logical normativity.

  12. What he calls the Logical Implication Principle (Harman 1986, p. 11).

  13. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

  14. Doxastic norms may also underpin appraisals of doxastic conduct.

  15. “To endorse the premises of a valid argument but to reject the conclusion is to contradict yourself in the following sense: There is no case in which those claims could hold true. Your commitments undercut themselves. (Beall and Restall 2006, p. 24)”

  16. When they introduce the criterion of normativity, Beall and Restall (2006, p. 16) give this gloss: “[I]f an argument is valid, then you somehow go wrong if you accept the premises but reject the conclusion.”

  17. Although this strikes me as the right thing to say, it could perhaps be contested. Proponents of situation semantics, e.g. Barwise and Perry (1983), might baulk at this claim. Suffice to say, it is a delicate issue.

  18. Shapiro (2014b) actually has a lot to say about the interaction between contexts, theories, and logics. A whole chapter of his book is devoted to resolving the Quinean charge of ‘meaning change’ between logics by appeal to contexts of intra-theoretic mathematical discourse. When I say that his remarks are made in passing, I am only referring to his remarks about how Beall and Restall’s account of “valid” resembles contextualist treatments of terms like “rude” or “tasty”. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me to clarify this point.

  19. Representative examples include Cohen (1988) and DeRose (1992), but the view of Lewis (1996) is closest to what I have in mind. See Ichikawa (2011) on the centrality of quantifier-variance to Lewis’ view. For a recent defense of a contextualist semantics for ‘knows’ see Schaffer and Szabo (2013).

  20. There are some who would not grant this. Goddu (2002) criticizes Beall and Restall for failing to provide sufficiently informative criteria to distinguish acceptable from unacceptable specifications of cases. Griffiths (2013) argues that the appeal to tradition is more of a hindrance than a help. He claims that every one of the features in the ‘historically settled core’ has been contested at some point in the history of logic.

  21. Lewis (1996, p. 559).

  22. Lewis (1996, p. 554).

  23. Field (2009a) also offers something like a contextualist account of logic, but it is rather different from the view on offer here. Field’s view does not explicitly appeal to the context-sensitivity of the concept of logical validity. This could not explain the plurality of logics, according to Field (2015), because the concept of logical validity is primitive and unanalyzable. Field’s view leads to something like attributer-relativity of logic, whereas the grounds of varying deductive standards are not individualized on my view. Field is also highly restrictive about the extent of the plurality, where my view can easily incorporate a large plurality of consequence relations.

  24. Steinberger (forthcoming) argues that for Carnap, the normativity of logic is grounded in the fact that we voluntarily elect a logic as a framework constitutive of a way of thinking. This is an attractive way for someone with pluralistic inclinations to conceive of the grounds of logical normativity. Something akin to Carnapian voluntarism is at work in my contextualist view.

  25. Field (2009b, p. 344) uses the term ‘all-purpose’ for a conception on which logic is normative for reasoning in all domains, whereas Ryle (1954, pp. 115–116) and Haack (1978, p. 5) call this ‘topic-neutrality’.

  26. Subjecting us to Quine’s equivocation charge. See Quine (1986, p. 80).

  27. For reservations about minimalism, see Hjortland (2013).

  28. See Dunn (1993) for more on this proposal.

References

  • Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J., & Restall, G. (2000). Logical pluralism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 475–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caret, C. R., & Hjortland, O. T. (Eds.). (2015). Foundations of logical consequence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1937). Logical syntax of language (trans: Smeaton, Amethe). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd.

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. T. (2014). Should anti-realists be anti-realists about anti-realism? Erkenntnis, 79, 233–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 913–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1993). Star and perp: Two treatments of negation. Philosophical Perspectives, 7, 331–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2009a). Pluralism in logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 2, 342–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2009b). What is the normative role of logic? Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 83, 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2015). What is logical validity?’ In Caret and Hjortland (2015) (pp. 33–70).

  • Glanzberg, M. (2015). Logical consequence and natural language. In Caret and Hjortland (2015) (pp. 71–120).

  • Goddu, G. C. (2002). What exactly is logical pluralism? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80, 218–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, O. (2013). Problems for logical pluralism. History and Philosophy of Logic, 34, 170–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1978). Philosophy of logics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1984). Logic and reasoning. Synthese, 60, 107–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hjortland, O. T. (2013). Logical pluralism, meaning-variance, and verbal disputes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 355–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. (2011). Quantifiers and epistemic contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 155, 383–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keefe, R. (2014). What logical pluralism cannot be. Synthese, 191, 1375–1390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2004). In what sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? Unpublished draft of April 21, 2004, Retrieved from http://johnmacfarlane.net/work.html.

  • Priest, G. (2001). Logic: One or many? In J. Woods & B. Brown (Eds.), Logical consequences: Rival approaches (pp. 23–38). Oxford: Hermes Scientific Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2006). Doubt truth to be a liar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1986). Philosophy of logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (2006). Monism: The one true logic. In D. DeVidi & T. Kenyon (Eds.), A logical approach to philosophy: Essays in honour of Graham Solomon (pp. 193–209). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (2002). Carnap’s tolerance, meaning, and logical pluralism. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 426–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (2014). Pluralism and proofs. Erkenntnis, 79, 279–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, G. (2008). One true logic? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 37, 593–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1954). Dilemmas: The tarner lectures 1953. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J., & Szabo, Z. G. (2013). Epistemic comparativism: A contextualist semantics for knowledge ascriptions. Philosophical Studies, 168, 491–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2014a). Structures and logics: A case for (a) relativism. Erkenntnis, 79, 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2014b). Varieties of logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steinberger, F. (forthcoming). Frege and Carnap on the normativity of logic. Synthese.

  • Steinberger, F. (2015). Three ways logic might be normative. Unpublished draft of January 27, 2015, retrieved from https://birkbeck.academia.edu/FlorianSteinberger.

  • Wedgwood, R. (2002). The aim of belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 267–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2007). Normativism defended. In B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 85–101). London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the following people for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper: Jamin Asay, Ben Burgis, Aiste Celkyte, Petr Cintula, Roy Cook, Yasuo Deguchi, Jiwon Kim, Hitoshi Omori, Nikolaj Pedersen, Jisoo Seo, Zach Weber, and Jeremy Wyatt.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Colin R. Caret.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Caret, C.R. The Collapse of Logical Pluralism has been Greatly Exaggerated. Erkenn 82, 739–760 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9841-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9841-7

Keywords

Navigation