Skip to main content
Log in

The Moral Terrain of Science

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The moral terrain of science, the full range of ethical considerations that are part of the scientific endeavor, has not been mapped. Without such a map, we cannot examine the responsibilities of scientists to see if the institutions of science are adequately constructed. This paper attempts such a map by describing four dimensions of the terrain: (1) the bases to which scientists are responsible (scientific reasoning, the scientific community, and the broader society); (2) the nature of the responsibility (general or role); (3) the level of responsibility (minimum demand or ideal); and (4) who bears the responsibility (the individual or the community). Such a map will be used to elucidate the recent debate over the publication of studies concerning H5N1 flu virus.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A task some have already begun, see, e.g. Elliott (2011), Kourany (2010), Fehr and Plaisance (2010).

  2. White lies about evidence are unacceptable, but it is debated whether deception in other aspects of scientific work is acceptable. For example, deception may be essential to some studies in the social sciences, and whether deceiving subjects in these cases is okay is contested. See Baumrind (1985), Wendler (1996), Wendler and Miller (2004). Deceiving subjects in other studies is generally not. For example, in RCTs, it is essential to informed consent that we tell patients that they are being randomly assigned to different study populations, which may include a placebo. Efforts to make the placebo indistinguishable from the treatment is not an act of deception in this context. Whether using deception to study the placebo effect itself is acceptable is another issue. See Miller et al. 2005. That there are these debates is beside the main point, that role responsibilities for scientists add additional honesty burdens.

  3. Whether scientists have more exacting role responsibilities to the broader society, such as that their research benefit society, seems to be in flux, evidenced by evolving codes of conduct, but it depends on the subdiscipline what the codes are. See, e.g. Kourany 2010, pp. 111–112.

  4. Because a license to do science would amount to a license to conduct empirical inquiry, and because it is important for the robustness of inquiry that such an ability be open to all comers, creating licensing barriers to do science seems a bad idea. Nor is it even clear it could be enforceable that only licensed scientists conduct empirical inquiry—what would constitute proper boundaries around inquiry activities? Scientists might be licensed to work with particular materials or in particular contexts, but not to do science generally as such.

  5. Thinking of societal benefit as an ideal, rather than a minimum, likely puts me in disagreement with Janet Kourany’s socially responsible science standard. See Kourany (2010), Brown (2012).

  6. I will not address here whether the research should have been conducted, whether it should continue, or whether biosecurity containment at the labs where the research was done, and will continue, is adequate. These are clearly weighty issues as well. The argument that organisms as dangerous as the new strains of H5N1 require at least a biosecurity rating of Level 4 (BSL4) are particularly crucial. See, e.g., Murillo (2012).

  7. Some also suggested it would be unprecedented, but that is not true. See Kaiser and Moreno 2012.

  8. It is important to note that the NSABB could not order the journals (Science and Nature both had accepted manuscripts at issue) to withhold or redact publications. But the journals agreed that if the NSABB did recommend limited publication, they would abide by the NSABB’s decision.

References

  • Baumrind, D. (1985). Research using intentional deception: Ethical issues revisited. American Psychologist, 40(2), 165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. (2012). The source and status of values in Kourany’s socially responsible science. Philosophical Studies, 163(1), 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brumfiel, G. (2012). Good science/bad science. Nature, 484(7395), 432–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2012). The limits of avian flu studies in ferrets. Science, 335(6068), 512–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2003). The moral responsibilities of scientists (tensions between autonomy and responsibility). American Philosophical Quarterly, 59–68.

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Reintroducing prediction to explanation. Philosophy of Science, 76, 444–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2010). Engagement for progress: applied philosophy of science in context. Synthese, 177(3), 317–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? incorporating societal values in environmental research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Enserink, M. (2011). Controversial studies give a deadly flu virus wings. Science, 334(6060), 1192–1193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fauci, A. S., & Collins, F. S. (2012). Benefits and risks of influenza research: Lessons learned. Science, 336(6088), 1522–1523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. (2011). What is in it for me? The benefits of diversity in scientific communities. In H. E. Grasswick (Ed.), Feminist epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 133–155). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C., & Plaisance, K. S. (2010). Socially relevant philosophy of science: An introduction. Synthese, 177(3), 301–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grady, D. (2012). Panel Says Flu Research is Safe to Publish. New York Times. Published March 30, 2012.

  • Greenfieldboyce, N. (2012). Dutch government set to reconsider restrictions on publishing bird flu study. NPR Shots Blog. http://www.npr.org/blogs/health/2012/04/20/151049741/dutch-government-set-to-reconsider-its-ban-on-publishing-bird-flu-study.

  • Hansen, L. A. (2013). Institution animal care and use committees need greater ethical diversity. Journal of Medical Ethics, 39(3), 188–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardimon, M. (1994). Role obligations. The Journal of Philosophy, XCI(7), 333–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holbrook, J. B. (2005). Assessing the science–society relation: the case of the US National Science Foundation’s second merit review criterion. Technology in Society, 27(4), 437–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holbrook, J. B. (Ed.) (2009). Special issue on the U.S. national science foundation’s broader impacts criterion. Social Epistemology, (Vol. 23, pp. 3–4).

  • Horner, J., & Minifie, F. D. (2011). Research ethics I: Responsible conduct of research (RCR)—Historical and contemporary issues pertaining to human and animal experimentation. Journal of Speech, Language, and Hearing Research, 54, S303–S329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intemann, K. (2009). Why diversity matters: Understanding and applying the diversity component of the National Science Foundation’s broader impacts criterion. Social Epistemology, 23(3–4), 249–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G. (2010). Why should philosophers of science pay attention to the commercialization of academic science? EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science, 129–138.

  • Kaiser, D., & Moreno, J. (2012). Dual-use research: Self-censorship is not enough. Nature, 492(7429), 345–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2004). Responsible biology. BioScience, 54(4), 331–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2010). Philosophy of science after feminism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, S. A. (1980). Moral responsibility and the “Galilean imperative”. Ethics, 100–116.

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macrina, F. L. (2000). Scientific integrity: An introductory text with cases. American Society for Microbiology.

  • McKay, C. (1995). The Evolution of the institutional review board: A brief overview of its history. Clinical Research and Regulatory Affairs, 12(2), 65–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, F. G., Wendler, D., & Swartzman, L. C. (2005). Deception in research on the placebo effect. PLoS Medicine, 2(9), e262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murillo, L. N. (2012). Ferret-Transmissible Influenza A (H5N1) Virus: Let us err on the side of caution. mBio, 3(2).

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. London: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pimple, K. D. (2002). Six domains of research ethics. Science and Engineering Ethics, 8(2), 191–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (2010). The commodification of academic research. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D. B. (1998). The ethics of science: an introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schienke, E. W., Tuana, N., Brown, D. A., Davis, K. J., Keller, K., Shortle, J. S., et al. (2009). The role of the national science foundation broader impacts criterion in enhancing research ethics pedagogy. Social Epistemology, 23(3–4), 317–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. S. (1994). Ethics of scientific research. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Pub Incorporated.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2006). Norms of epistemic diversity. Episteme, 3(1–2), 23–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2012). Socially responsible science and the unity of values. Perspectives on Science, 20(3), 331–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D. (1996). Deception in medical and behavioral research: Is it ever acceptable? The Milbank Quarterly, 87–114.

  • Wendler, D., & Miller, F. G. (2004). Deception in the pursuit of science. Archives of Internal Medicine, 164(6), 597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolinetz, C. D. (2012). Implementing the New US dual-use policy. Science, 336(6088), 1525–1527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper evolved at a series of talks I gave at Center for Interdisciplinary Research (ZiF) at the Universität Bielefeld (at a conference on “The Social Relevance of Philosophy of Science” organized by Martin Carrier and Don Howard), the Department of Philosophy at the University of Cincinnatti (at their 49th Annual Philosophy Colloquium colloquium on socially engaged philosophy of science organized by Angela Potochnik), the Department of Philosophy at the University of Guelph (organized by Maya Goldenberg), and at the Department of Philosophy at the University of Alberta (organized by Ingo Brigandt). My thanks to all those who organized these events and to the audiences who provided such helpful feedback. This paper also benefited from the comments of Doreen Fraser, Marc Lipsitch, Ted Richards, two anonymous referees, and the feedback from my students of PHIL 271 Science in Society Winter 2013 at the University of Waterloo.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Heather Douglas.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Douglas, H. The Moral Terrain of Science. Erkenn 79 (Suppl 5), 961–979 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9538-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9538-0

Keywords

Navigation