Skip to main content
Log in

Utilitarian Traits and the Janus-Headed Model: Origins, Meaning, and Interpretation

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Two distinct and perhaps mutually exclusive understandings of utilitarianism have emerged in the ethics literature. Utilitarianism is typically regarded as an approach to determine ethicality by focusing on whether or not actions produce the greater good, but has also been conceptualized as a set of traits to which individuals might be predisposed. This paper is designed to clarify the meaning and implications of such utilitarian traits as “results-oriented,” “innovative,” and “a winner.” Although the Janus-headed model of ethical theory from which these traits emerged had been acknowledged by its developer as possibly misrepresenting typical views of utilitarianism, much research using these traits appears to have been conducted without clear recognition of this. If the conceptual foundation underpinning hypothesis development is disconnected from the measure used to test them, then little support for relevant predictions should emerge. A review of the literature which featured utilitarian traits generally confirmed this. This paper also explored the origins and emergence of these traits and suggested that existing evidence that these measure utilitarian ethical predispositions is not especially persuasive. Understanding what utilitarian traits do not assess is critical in order for knowledge about this potentially useful measure to advance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Brady (1985) did not specify the precise meaning of “classic” or “traditional” views of utilitarianism, and did not identify the proponents of such views. An overview of all possible ethical models generally and all variants in utilitarianism specifically (e.g., “preference”, “ideal”, or “world” utilitarianism; Sinnott-Armstrong 2015), including the extent to which utilitarianism might incorporate self-interest in some interpretations, is beyond the scope of this paper. However, Mill’s ideas on the subject seem adequate for gaining a basic understanding of the conceptual foundation from which utilitarian traits emerged. Utilitarianism, after all, “is primarily based on the writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill” (Schwartz and Carroll 2008, p. 159; see also Carroll and Buchholtz 2015, Chapter 8); that is, the “Classical Utilitarians” (Driver 2014). Many researchers who have used the utilitarian traits measure also referred to Mill by name (discussed later in the paper), and thus appear to have regarded, perhaps implicitly, Mill’s approach as adequate for the purposes of providing background.

  2. Nozick’s reference to “two powerful molds” has seemed important in the context of research into utilitarian traits, and was discussed by Alder et al. (2007, 2008), Schminke (2001), Schminke et al. (2003, 1997), and Wiltermuth et al. (2013).

  3. Schminke and Wells (1999) and Schminke et al. (2002) both considered the impact of leadership on changes in utilitarianism and formalism in student groups over time, and focused on changes in trait scores at the group level. Schminke et al. (2003) asked participants to think about an ethical dilemma that occurred away from work, and to respond to MEV items in that specific context rather than as to how they would normally respond. Cojuharenco et al. (2012) had respondents indicate the importance of traits that describe others rather than themselves. Wiltermuth et al. (2013, p. 289) and Xu and Ma (2016, p. 541) mentioned using the Brady and Wheeler (1996) measure, but did not appear to have discussed any pertinent results. Xu and Ma (2016, Table 2) operationalized “utilitarianism” as a dichotomous variable, with “1” representing “utilitarianism” and “0” suggesting “deontology”.

  4. Two additional measures of ‘utilitarianism’ are the Survey of Ethical Theoretic Aptitudes (Brady 1990) used, for example, by Love et al. (2016), Schminke (1997), and Smith et al. (2009), and the single-item Baugher and Weisbord (2009) measure (“The greatest good for the greatest number is the only proper measure of right and wrong”) used by Wiltermuth et al. (2013). As no evidence appears to have yet been provided about the extent to which MEV utilitarian trait scores correlate with these other measures, these measures are not discussed further.

  5. The construct assessed with utilitarian traits has been referred to as “ethical viewpoints” (Schminke 2001), “moral orientation” (Wiltermuth and Flynn 2013), and variations on the term “consequentialism” (Albert et al. 2015; Reynolds and Ceranic 2007; Reynolds et al. 2014; Ruedy and Schweitzer 2010; Verbos and Miller 2015). Regardless of the nomenclature used, each of these terms referred to the construct assessed with utilitarian traits developed by Brady and Wheeler (1996).

  6. Although Alder et al. (2008) predicted that utilitarian traits would moderate the positive relationships between the perceived usefulness of internet monitoring and four outcome measures, these predicted positive relationships did not actually emerge. The largest of four relevant correlations was .05 (Table 1, p. 491). Moreover, two of the three items in the measure of monitoring usefulness had no relevance to internet monitoring. As results cannot be interpreted unambiguously, the partial hypothesis support reported in this study seems of limited relevance to determining whether or not utilitarian traits assess utilitarian ethical predispositions.

  7. The mean “frequency of cheating” score among college students in Study 1 was 1.42 with a standard deviation of 0.31. A score two standard deviations above the mean equaled 2.04 on a four-point scale (“1” = never, “4” = many times), and thus there was a low frequency of admitted cheating in this sample. The positive relationship between utilitarian trait scores and cheating frequency reported in regression analyses (r = .06, ns) can perhaps be interpreted to suggest that high trait scorers had rarely or sometimes cheated (the precise meaning of a score of “2” was not specified).

  8. Schminke et al. (1997, p. 1203) “speculate[d] about the reasons” for unexpected negative relationships between fairness in respondents’ own organizations and MEV scores, and noted that “further research is needed to address” why “higher ethical scores may result in lower perceptions of procedural and distributive fairness”. However, as low justice scores implied “very” fair procedures and outcomes in one’s own organization (p. 1196), speculation or further research seemed unnecessary. Actual results corresponded with expectations, and high utilitarian trait scorers perceived work outcomes as fair rather than unfair.

  9. The complexity involved in determining an action’s ethicality from a utilitarian perspective implies the ability not only to identify benefits and harms from various courses of action to all relevant stakeholders, but also to weigh these to isolate the action providing the largest benefit-to-harm ratio. Ascertaining utilitarianism as preferable to other options such as the categorical imperative assumes that it is possible to: (1) use multiple approaches at more than a superficial level in real-world decision making; (2) understand the criteria that would make one approach ‘better than’ another; and (3) determine based on objective evidence that utilitarianism was indeed ‘better’. However, if the moral “theories that most people actually use are quite simple and vague” (Curzer 2014, p. 108) and “many people have trouble applying their moral theories correctly” (p. 107), then few people would seem able to conclude with certainty that utilitarianism is ‘best’.

  10. Different ethical approaches would likely tend to produce the same conclusion about an action’s ethicality in many, if not most, cases. Many actions prohibited by ethical norms, after all, tend to create harms, and individuals with different preferences would be in total agreement that such actions would be unethical. When disagreement did exist, an action that appears ethically permissible to one person because it promotes more benefit than harm might seem unethical to another because it violates one or more norms. However, such disagreement would have little real-world import if different preferences led to the same action (or no action). People differ in their “moral motivation” (Rest et al. 1999, p. 101) to translate beliefs about ethicality into behavior, and not everyone would necessarily perform ethically questionable actions even though they seem to produce the greater good.

References

  • Albert, L. S., Reynolds, S. J., & Turan, B. (2015). Turning inward or focusing out? Navigating theories of interpersonal and ethical cognitions to understand ethical decision-making. Journal of Business Ethics, 130(2), 467–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alder, G. S., Schminke, M., & Noel, T. W. (2007). The impact of individual ethics on reactions to potentially invasive HR practices. Journal of Business Ethics, 75(2), 201–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alder, G. S., Schminke, M., Noel, T. W., & Kuenzi, M. (2008). Employee reactions to internet monitoring: The moderating role of ethical orientation. Journal of Business Ethics, 80(3), 481–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baugher, D., & Weisbord, E. (2009). Egoism, justice, rights, and utilitarianism: Student views of classic ethical positions in business. Journal of Academic and Business Ethics, 1(1), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, F. N. (1985). A Janus-headed model of ethical theory: Looking two ways at business/society issues. Academy of Management Review, 10(3), 568–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, F. N. (1990). Ethical managing: Rules and results. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, F. N., & Dunn, C. P. (1995). Business meta-ethics: An analysis of two theories. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(3), 385–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, F. N., & Wheeler, G. E. (1996). An empirical study of ethical predispositions. Journal of Business Ethics, 15(9), 927–940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, A. B., & Buchholtz, A. K. (2015). Business and society: Ethics, sustainability, and stakeholder management (9th ed.). Stamford, CT: Cengage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christian, J. S., & Ellis, A. P. J. (2014). The crucial role of turnover intentions in transforming moral disengagement into deviant behavior at work. Journal of Business Ethics, 119(2), 193–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cojuharenco, I., Shteynberg, G., Gelfand, M., & Schminke, M. (2012). Self-construal and unethical behavior. Journal of Business Ethics, 109(4), 447–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cronbach, L. J., & Meehl, P. E. (1955). Construct validity in psychological tests. Psychological Bulletin, 52(4), 281–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cropanzano, R., & Stein, J. H. (2009). Organizational justice and behavioral ethics: Promises and prospects. Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(2), 193–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, H. J. (2014). Tweaking the four-component model. Journal of Moral Education, 43(1), 104–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2014). The history of utilitarianism. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/utilitarianism-history/.

  • Fritzsche, D. J., & Becker, H. (1984). Linking management behavior to ethical philosophy: An empirical investigation. Academy of Management Journal, 27(1), 166–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G., Jr. (2003). Scientific method in practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T. M. (1991). Ethical decision making by individuals in organizations: An issue-contingent model. Academy of Management Review, 16(2), 366–395.

  • Langlais, P. J., & Bent, B. J. (2014). Individual and organizational predictors of the ethicality of graduate students’ responses to research integrity issues. Science and Engineering Ethics, 20(4), 897–921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, V. P., & Wong, Y. Y. (2009). Direct and multiplicative effects of ethical dispositions and ethical climates on personal justice norms: A virtue ethics perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 90(2), 279–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Letwin, C., Wo, D., Folger, R., Rice, D., Taylor, R., Richard, B., et al. (2016). The “right” and the “good” in ethical leadership: Implications for supervisors’ performance and promotability evaluations. Journal of Business Ethics, 137(4), 743–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, E., Staton, M., & Rotman, J. D. (2016). Loyalty as a matter of principle: The influence of standards of judgment on customer loyalty. Marketing Letters, 27(4), 661–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowry, P. B., Posey, C., Roberts, T. L., & Bennett, R. J. (2014). Is your banker leaking your personal information? The roles of ethics and individual-level cultural characteristics in predicting organizational computer abuse. Journal of Business Ethics, 121(3), 385–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFerran, B., Aquino, K., & Duffy, M. (2010). How personality and moral identity relate to individuals’ ethical ideology. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(1), 35–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1863/1969). Utilitarianism. In J.M. Robson (Ed.), Essays on ethics, religion and society by John Stuart Mill (Vol. 10, pp. 203–259). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearsall, M. J., & Ellis, A. P. J. (2011). Thick as thieves: The effects of ethical orientation and psychological safety on unethical team behavior. Journal of Applied Psychology, 96(2), 401–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rest, J., Narvaez, D., Bebeau, M. J., & Thoma, S. J. (1999). Postconventional moral thinking: A neo-Kohlbergian approach. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. J. (2006). Moral awareness and ethical predispositions: Investigating the role of individual differences in the recognition of moral issues. Journal of Applied Psychology, 91(1), 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. J. (2008). Moral attentiveness: Who pays attention to the moral aspects of life? Journal of Applied Psychology, 93(5), 1027–1041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. J., & Ceranic, T. L. (2007). The effects of moral judgment and moral identity on moral behavior: An empirical examination of the moral individual. Journal of Applied Psychology, 92(6), 1610–1624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. J., Dang, C. T., Yam, K. C., & Leavitt, K. (2014). The role of moral knowledge in everyday immorality: What does it matter if I know what is right? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 123(2), 124–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruedy, N. E., & Schweitzer, M. E. (2010). In the moment: The effect of mindfulness on ethical decision making. Journal of Business Ethics, 95((1, Supplement)), 73–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M. (1997). Gender differences in ethical frameworks and evaluations of others’ choices in ethical dilemmas. Journal of Business Ethics, 16(1), 55–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M. (2001). Considering the business in business ethics: An exploratory study of the influence of organizational size and structure on individual ethical predispositions. Journal of Business Ethics, 30(4), 375–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M., Ambrose, M. L., & Miles, J. A. (2003). The impact of gender and setting on perceptions of others’ ethics. Sex Roles, 48(7–8), 361–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M., Ambrose, M. L., & Noel, T. W. (1997). The effect of ethical frameworks on perceptions of organizational justice. Academy of Management Journal, 40(5), 1190–1207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M., & Wells, D. (1999). Group processes and performance and their effects on individuals’ ethical frameworks. Journal of Business Ethics, 18(4), 367–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schminke, M., Wells, D., Peyrefitte, J., & Sebora, T. C. (2002). Leadership and ethics in work groups: A longitudinal assessment. Group and Organization Management, 27(2), 272–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, M. S., & Carroll, A. B. (2008). Integrating and unifying competing and complementary frameworks: The search for a common core in the business and society field. Business and Society, 47(2), 148–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2015). Consequentialism. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/consequentialism/.

  • Smith, C. G., Sumilo, E., & Karnups, V. P. (2009). Moral judgment: A comparison of Latvian and US business persons. Baltic Journal of Management, 4(2), 188–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbos, A. K., & Miller, J. S. (2015). When harm is at stake: Ethical value orientation, managerial decisions, and relational outcomes. Journal of Business Ethics, 127(1), 149–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, G. F., & Brady, F. N. (1998). Do public-sector and private-sector personnel have different ethical dispositions? A study of two sites. Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, 8(1), 93–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiltermuth, S. S., Bennett, V. M., & Pierce, L. (2013). Doing as they would do: How the perceived ethical preferences of third-party beneficiaries impact ethical decision-making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Process, 122(2), 280–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiltermuth, S. S., & Flynn, F. J. (2013). Power, moral clarity, and punishment in the workplace. Academy of Management Journal, 56(4), 1002–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worden, S. (2009). A genealogy of business ethics: A Nietzschean perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(3), 427–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, Z. X., & Ma, H. K. (2016). How can a deontological decision lead to moral behavior? The moderating role of moral identity. Journal of Business Ethics, 137(3), 537–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, L., & Gowan, M. A. (2012). Corporate social responsibility, applicants’ individual traits, and organizational attraction: A person-organization fit perspective. Journal of Business and Psychology, 27(3), 345–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors wish to thank Diane Swanson, editor R. Edward Freeman, and four anonymous reviewers for valuable comments on earlier versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter E. Mudrack.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mudrack, P.E., Mason, E.S. Utilitarian Traits and the Janus-Headed Model: Origins, Meaning, and Interpretation. J Bus Ethics 156, 227–240 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3592-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3592-5

Keywords

Navigation